THE LOGIC OF HEGEL WALLACE Bonbon HENRY FROWDE OXFORD UNIVERSITY PRESS WAREHOUSE AMEN CORNER, E.G. MACMILLAN & Co., 66 FIFTH AVENUE .ot^vc o^ He^el tVbL Kl PROLEGOMENA TO THE STUDY OF HEGEL'S PHILOSOPHY AND ESPECIALLY OF HIS LOGIC BY WILLIAM WALLACE, M.A., LL.D. FELLOW OF MERTON COLLEGE AND WHYTE'S PROFESSOR OF MORAL PHILOSOPHY IN THE UNIVERSITY OF OXFORD SECOND EDITION, REVISED AND AUGMENTED AT THE CLARENDON PRESS 1894 I 4 3 S \JO i 2- PRINTED AT THE CLARENDON PRESS BY HORACE HART, PRINTER TO THE UNIVERSITY IN REMEMBRANCE OF B. JOWETT LATE REGIUS PROFESSOR OF GREEK AND MASTER OF BALLIOL COLLEGE OXFORD PREFACE THE present volume of Prolegomena completes the second edition of my LOGIC OF HEGEL which originally appeared in 1874. The translation, which was issued as a separate volume in the autumn of 1892, had been subjected to revision throughout : such faults as I could detect had been amended, and many changes made in the form of expression with the hope of rendering the interpretation clearer and more adequate. But, with a subject so abstruse and complicated as Hegel's Logic, and a style so abrupt and condensed as that adopted in his Encyclopaedia, a satisfactory translation can hardly fall within the range of possibilities. Only the enthusiasm of youth could have thrown itself upon such an enterprise; and later years have but to do what they may to fulfil the obligations of a task whose difficulties have come to seem nearly in superable. The translation volume was introduced by a sketch of the growth of the Encyclopaedia through the three editions published in its author's lifetime : and an appendix of notes supplied some literary and historical elucidations of the text, with quotations bearing on the philosophical development between Kant and Hegel. viii PREFACE. The Prolegomena, which have grown to more than twice their original extent, are two-thirds of them new matter. The lapse of twenty years could not but involve a change in the writer's attitude, at least in details, towards both facts and problems. The general purpose of the work, however, still remains the same, to supply an introduction to the study of Hegel, especially his Logic, and to philosophy in general. But, in the work of altering and inserting, I can hardly imagine that I have succeeded in adjusting the additions to the older work with that artful junc ture which would simulate the continuity of organic growth. To perform that feat would require a master who surveyed from an imperial outlook the whole system of Hegelianism in its history and meaning ; and I at least do not profess such a mastery. Prob ably therefore a critical review will discern inequalities in the ground, and even discrepancies in the statement, of the several chapters. To remove these strains of inconsistency would in any case have been a work of time and trouble : and, after all, mere differences in depth or breadth of view may have their uses. The writer cannot always compel the reader to understand him, as he himself has not always the same faculty to penetrate and comprehend the problems he deals with. In these arduous paths of research it may well happen that the clearest and truest perceptions are not always those which communicate themselves with fullest persuasion and gift of insight. Schopenhauer has somewhere compared the structure of his philo sophical work to the hundred-gated Thebes : so many, he says, are the points of access it offers for the PREFACE. IX pilgrims after truth to reach its central dogma. So — if one may parallel little things with his adventurous quest— even the less speculative chapters, and the less consecutive discourse, of these Prolegomena may prove helpful to some individual mood or phase of mind. If — as I suspect — the Second Book should elicit the complaint that the reader has been kept wandering too long and too deviously in the Porches of Philosophy, I will hope that sometimes in the course of these rovings he may come across a wicket-gate where he can enter, and — which is the main thing — gather truth fresh and fruitful for himself. Fourteen chapters, viz. II, XXIV, and the group from VII to XVIII inclusive, are in this edition almost entirely new. Three chapters of the first edition, numbered XIX, XXII, XXIII, have been dropped. For the rest, Chaps. III-VI in the present cor respond to Chaps. II-V in the first edition : Chap. XIX to parts of VII, VIII: Chaps. XX-XXIII to Chaps. IX-XII : Chaps. XXV-XXX to Chaps. XIII- XVIII: and Chaps. XXXI, XXXII to Chaps. XX, XXI. But some of those nominally retained have been largely rewritten. The new chapters present, amongst other things, a synopsis of the progress of thought in Germany during the half-century which is bisected by the year 1800, with some indication of the general conditions of the intellectual world, and with some reference to the inter connexion of speculation and actuality. Jacobi and Herder, Kant, Fichte, and Schelling have been especi ally brought under succinct review. In the first edition I did Kant less than justice. I have now, so far as my X PREFACE. limits allowed, tried to rectify the impression; and even more perhaps, by a clear palinode, to tender my apology for the meagre and somewhat inapprecia- tive notice I gave to the great names of Fichte and Schelling. For like reasons, and from a growing per ception how much post-Kantian thought owed to the pre-Kantian thinkers, Spinoza and Leibniz have been partly brought within my range. If, furthermore, I may seem to have transgressed the due amount of allusions and comparisons drawn from Plato and Aristotle, Bacon and Mill, the excuse must be sought in that fixture of philosophical horizon which can hardly but creep on after a quarter of a century spent in teaching philosophy under the customs and ordi nances of the Oxford School of Classical Philology. It would be to mistake the scope of this survey to seek in it a history of the philosophers of the period I have named. They have been presented, not in and for themselves, but as momenta or constituent factors in producing Hegel's conceptioji__of thp aim and method of philosophy. To do this it was neces sary to lay stress on their inner purport and implica tions : to treat the individual thinker in subordination to the general movement of ideas : to give, as far as was possible, a constructive conception of them rather than an analysis and chronicle. .Yet as the picture had to be done, so to say, with a few vigorous touches, and made characteristic rather than descriptive, it can not have that fairness and completeness which only patient study of every feature and untiring experiment in reconstruction can enable even the artist to produce. I may have seemed to confine the environment too PREFACE. XI exclusively to continental thinkers : but this is not, I think, due to any anti-patriotic bias. English (by which term, I may explain to my countrymen, I mean English-writing) thought, if it has its own intrinsic value, has after all been only an occasional influence, of suggestion and modification, in Germany. It is not therefore an integral portion of my theme. Even in Kant's case, too much may be made of the stimulus he received from Hume. Even twenty years ago, my translation could hardly be described literally as a voice crying in the wilder ness. But since that time there has been a considerable out-put of history, translation, and criticism referring to the great age of German philosophy, and a compara tively numerous group of writers, more or less familiar with the aims and principles of that period, have treated various parts of philosophy with notable independence and originality. To these writers it has sometimes been found convenient to give the title of Neo- Kantians, or Neo- Hegelians. The prefix suggests that they do not in all points reproduce the ideal or the caricature which vulgar tradition fancied, and perhaps still fancies, to be implied in German 'transcendentalism.' And that for the good reason that the springs of the movement lie in the natural and national revulsion of English habits of mind. Slowly, but at length, the storms of the great European revolution found their way to our intellectual world, and shook church and state, society and literature. The homeless spirit of the age had to reconsider the task of rebuilding its house of life. It may have been that some of the seekers, in the fervour of a first impression, spoke Xll PREFACE. unadvisedly, as if salvation could and would come to English philosophy only by Kant and Hegel. Yet, there was a real foundation for the belief that the insularity — however necessary in its season, and how ever admirable in some of its results — which had secluded and narrowed the British mind since the middle of the eighteenth century, needed something deeper and stronger than French 'ideology' to bring it abreast of the requirements of the age. Whatever may be the drawbacks of transcendentalism, they are virtues when set beside the vulgar ideals of enlighten ment by superficialisation. Mill has well pointed out how the spirit of Coleridge was for the higher intel lectual life a needful complement to the spirit of Bentham. Yet the spirit of Coleridge had but caught some of the side-lights and romantic illuminations : it had not dared to face the central sun either in litera ture or philosophy. The scholar who has given us excellent versions of Fichte's lighter works, those who have translated and expounded Kant, and the great author who opened German literature to the British public, have brought us nearer the higher teaching of Germany. In Germany itself it has always been the possession only of the few. Even at the height of the classical period there were litterateurs who vended thousands of their books for Goethe's hun dreds, and the great philosophers had ten opponents to one follower even amongst the teachers of their day. Yet Goethe and not Kotzebue gave the permanent law to literature; Hegel, and not Krug or Fries, has influenced philosophy. To have had the resolution to learn in this school is the merit of 'Neo-Hegelianism.' PREFACE. xiii It has probably not found Kant free from puzzles and contradictions, or Hegel always intelligible. But the example of the Germans has served to widen and deepen our ideas of philosophy: to make us think more highly of its function, and to realise that it is essentially science, and the science of supreme reality. And it has at least familiarised many with the heresy that dilettantism and occasional fits of speculativeness are worth as little in philosophy as elsewhere. To have striven for dignity in its scope, and scientific security in its method, is something. If the Neo-Hegelian has not given philosophy a settled language, it may be urged that a philosophical language cannot be created by the easy device of inventing a few Hellenistic- seeming vocables. I could have wished to make these volumes a worthier contribution to the work whereby these and other writers have recently enriched our island philo sophy. Not least because of the honoured name I have ventured to write on the dedication-page. If, as Epicurus said, we should above all be grateful to the past, the first meed is from the scholar due to the teachers of earlier years, and not least those who have now entered into their rest. I do not forget what I, and others, owed to T. H. Green, my predecessor in the Chair of Moral Philosophy ; that example of high- souled devotion to truth, and of earnest and intrepid thinking on the deep things of eternity. But at this season the memory of my Oxford tutor and friend is naturally most prominent. The late Master of Balliol College was more than a mere scholar or a mere philosopher. He seemed so idealist and yet so prac- xiv PREFACE. tical : so realist and yet so full of high ideals : so delicately kind and yet so severely reasonable. You felt he saw life more steadily and saw it more whole than others : as one reality in which religion and philosophy, art and business, the sciences and theo logy, were severally but elements and aspects. To the amateurs of novelty, to the slaves of specialisation, to the devotees of any narrow way, such largeness might, with the impatience natural to limited minds, have seemed indifference. So must appear those who on higher planes hear all the parts in the harmony of humanity, and with the justice of a wise love maintain an intel lectual Sophrosyne. On his pupils this secret power of an other-world serenity laid an irresistible spell, and bore in upon them the conviction that beyond scholarship and logic there was the fuller truth of life and the all-embracing duty of doing their best to fulfil the amplest requirements of their place. In earlier days Jowett had been keenly interested in German philosophy, and had made a version (most of which was still extant in 1868) of the Logic I have translated. But Greek literature, and above all Plato, drew him to more congenial fields. It was on his suggestion, — or shall I say injunction ?— at that date, that the work I had casually begun was some years later prosecuted to completion. It was his words, again, two years ago, that bade me spare no labour in the work of revision. OXFORD, December, 1893. FROM THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION THE 'Logic of Hegel' is a name which may be given to two separate books. One of these is the 'Science of Logic' (Wissenschaft der Logik), first published in three volumes (1812-1816), while its author was schoolmaster at Nuremberg. A second edition was on its way, when Hegel was suddenly cut off, after revising the first volume only. In the ' Secret of Hegel/ the earlier part of this Logic has been translated by Dr. Hutchison Stirling, with whose name German philosophy is chiefly associated in this country. The other Logic, of which the present work is a translation, forms the First Part in the ' Encyclopaedia of the Philosophical Sciences/ The first edition of the Encyclopaedia appeared at Heidelberg in 1817 ; the second in 1827; and the third in 1830. It is well to bear in mind that these dates take us back forty or fifty years, to a time when modern science and Inductive Logic had yet to win their laurels, and when the world was in many ways different from what it is now. The earliest edition of the Encyclopaedia contained the pith of the system. The subsequent editions brought some new materials, mainly intended to smooth over and explain the transitions between the various sections, and to answer the objections of xvi FROM THE PREFACE TO THE FIRST EDITION". critics. The work contained a synopsis of philosophy in the form of paragraphs, and was to be supplemented by the viva voce remarks of the lecturer. The present volume is translated from the edition of 1843, forming the Sixth Volume in Hegel's Collected Works. It consists of two nearly equal portions. One half, here printed in more open type, contains Hegel's Encyclopaedia, with all the author's own additions. The first paragraph under each number marks the earliest and simplest statement of the first edition. The other half, here printed in closer type, is made up of the notes taken in lecture by the editor (Henning) and by Professors Hotho and Michelet. These notes for the most part connect the several sections, rather than explain their statements. Their genuineness is vouched for by their being almost verbally the same with other parts of Hegel's own writings. The translation has tried to keep as closely as possible to the meaning, without always adhering very rigorously to the words of the original. It is, however, much more literal in the later and systematic part, than in the earlier chapters. The Prolegomena which precede the translation have not been given in the hope or with the intention of expounding the Hegelian system. They merely seek to remove certain obstacles, and to render Hegel less tantalizingly hard to those who approach him for the first time. How far they will accomplish this, remains to be seen. OXFORD, September, 1873. CONTENTS BOOK I. OUTLOOKS AND APPROACHES TO HEGEL. CHAPTER I. PAGE WHY HEGEL is HARD TO UNDERSTAND ..... 3 CHAPTER II. WHY TRANSLATE HEGEL? 14 CHAPTER III. ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY AND HEGEL . 21 CHAPTER IV. HEGEL AND THEOLOGY 30 CHAPTER V. PSEUDO- IDEALISM: JACOBI 37 CHAPTER VI. THE SCIENCES AND PHILOSOPHY 57 CHAPTER VII. ANTICIPATORY SKETCH OF THE SCOPE OF PHILOSOPHY . 72 CHAPTER VIII. THE SCEPTICAL DOUBT : HUME 88 CHAPTER IX. THE ATTEMPT AT A CRITICAL SOLUTION : KANT ... 98 b xviii CONTENTS. CHAPTER X. PAGE THE CRITICAL SOLUTION (continued} : KANT .... 112 CHAPTER XI. SYNTHESIS AND RECONSTRUCTION : FICHTE .... 124 CHAPTER XII. THE BEGINNINGS OF SCHELLING 136 CHAPTER XIII. THE PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE AND IDEALISM .... 147 CHAPTER XIV. TRANSITION TO HEGEL ........ 163 BOOK II. IN THE PORCHES OF PHILOSOPHY. CHAPTER XV. THE Two AGES OF REASON ....... CHAPTER XVI. THE NEW IDEALISM 189 CHAPTER XVII. METHODS, ARTIFICIAL AND NATURAL 202 CHAPTER XVIII. THE RANGE OF PERSONALITY 230 CHAPTER XIX. GENESIS IN MENTAL LIFE 261 CHAPTER XX. GENERAL LAW OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY . . . 277 CHAPTER XXI. ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE : AND THE ORDINARY LOGIC . . 292 CONTENTS. xix CHAPTER XXII. FROM SENSE TO THOUGHT CHAPTER XXIII. FlGURATE OR REPRESENTATIVE THOUGHT .... 323 CHAPTER XXIV. FROM SUBSTANCE TO SUBJECT ....... 335 CHAPTER XXV. REASON AND THE DIALECTIC OF UNDERSTANDING . . . 348 BOOK III. LOGICAL OUTLINES. CHAPTER XXVI. THOUGHT PURE AND ENTIRE 365 CHAPTER XXVII. ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE : OR THE CATEGORIES . . . 383 CHAPTER XXVIII. THE THREE PARTS OF LOGIC 394 CHAPTER XXIX. THE SEARCH FOR A FIRST PRINCIPLE 404 CHAPTER XXX. THE LOGIC OF DESCRIPTION : NATURAL REALISM : BEING . 415 CHAPTER XXXI. THE LOGIC OF EXPLANATION AND REALISTIC METAPHYSICS : ESSENCE 440 CHAPTER XXXII. THE LOGIC OF COMPREHENSION AND IDEALISM : THE NOTION . 459 V ERRATUM P. 464. 1. 13. for the sense which read the sense in which PROLEGOMENA BOOK I OUTLOOKS AND APPROACHES TO HEGEL PROLEGOMENA CHAPTER I. WHY HEGEL IS HARD TO UNDERSTAND. 'THE condemnation/ says Hegel, 'which a great man lays upon the world, is to force it to explain him V The greatness of Hegel, if it be measured by this standard, must be something far above common. Inter preters of his system have contradicted each other, almost as variously as the several commentators on the Bible. He is claimed as their head by widely different schools of thought, all of which appeal to him as the original source of their line of argument. The Right wing, and the Left, as well as the Centre, profess to be the genuine descendants of the prophet, and to inherit the mantle of his inspiration. If we believe one side, Hegel is only to be rightly appreciated when we divest his teaching of every shred of religion and orthodoxy which it retains. If we believe another class of expo sitors, he was the champion of Christianity. These contradictory views may be safely left to abolish each other. But diversity of opinion on such topics is neither unnatural, nor unusual. The meaning and the bearings of a great event, or a great character, or a great work of reasoned thought, will be estimated and explained in different ways, according to the effect 1 Hegel's Leben (Rosenkranz), p. 555. B 2 4 PROLEGOMENA. [i. they produce on different minds and different levels of life and society. Those effects, perhaps, will not pre sent themselves in their true character, until long after the original excitement has passed away. To some minds, the chief value of the Hegelian system will lie in its vindication of the truths of natural and revealed religion, and in the agreement of the elaborate reason ings of the philosopher with the simple aspirations of mankind towards higher things. To others that system will have most interest as a philosophical history of thought, — an exposition of that organic development of reason, which underlies and constitutes all the varied and complex movement of the world. To a third class, again, it may seem at best an instrument or method of investigation, stating the true law by which knowledge proceeds in its endeavour to comprehend and assimilate existing nature. While these various meanings may be given to the Hegelian scheme of thought, the majority of the world either pronounce Hegel to be altogether unintelligible, or banish him to the limbo of a priori thinkers, — that bourne from which no philosopher returns. To argue with those who start from the latter conviction would be an ungrateful, and probably a superfluous task. Wisdom is justified, we may be sure, of all her chil dren. But it may be possible to admit the existence of difficulties, and agree to some extent with those who complain that Hegel is impenetrable and hard as ada mant. There can be no doubt of the forbidding aspect of the most prominent features in his system. He is hard in himself, and his readers find him hard. His style is not of the best, and to foreign eyes seems unequal. At times he is eloquent, stirring, and striking: again his turns are harsh, and his clauses tiresome to disentangle : and we are always coming upon that I.] THINKING IN VACUO. 5 childlikeness of literary manner, which English taste fancies it can detect in some of the greatest works of German genius. There are faults in Hegel, which obscure his meaning : but more obstacles are due to the nature of the work, and the pre-occupations of our minds. There is something in him which fascinates the thinker, and which inspires a sympathetic student with the vigour and the hopefulness of the spring-time. Perhaps the main hindrance in the way of a clear vision is the contrast which Hegelian philosophy offers to our ordinary habits of mind. Generally speaking, we rest contented if we can get tolerably near our object, and form a general picture of it to set before ourselves. It might almost be said that we have never thought of such a thing as being in earnest either with our words or with our thoughts. We get into a way of speaking with an uncertain latitude of meaning, and leave a good deal to the fellow-feeling of our hearers, who are ex pected to mend what is defective in our utterances. For most of us the place of exact thought is supplied by metaphors and pictures, by mental images, and figures generalised from the senses. And thus it happens that, when we come upon a single precise and definite statement, neither exceeding nor falling short in its meaning, we are thrown out of our reckon ing. Our fancy and memory have nothing left for them to do : and, as fancy and memory make up the greater part of what we loosely call thinking, our powers of thought seem to be brought to a standstill. Those who crave for fluent reading, or prefer easy writing, some thing within the pale of our usual mental lines, are more likely to find what they seek in the ten partially correct and approximate ways commonly used to give expression to a truth, than in the one simple and accurate statement of the thought. We prefer a 6 PROLEGOMENA. [i. familiar name, and an accustomed image, on which our faculties may work. But in the atmosphere of Hegelian thought, we feel very much as if we had been lifted into a vacuum, where we cannot breathe, and which is a fit habitation for unrecognisable ghosts only. Nor is this all. The traveller, as his train climbs the heights of Alps or Apennines, occasionally, after circling in grand curve upon the mountain-side, and perhaps after having been dragged mysterious distances through the gloom of a tunnel, finds himself as it would seem back at the same place as he looked forth from some minutes before ; and it is only after a brief comparison that he realises he now commands a wider view from a point some hundreds of feet higher. So the student of Hegel — (and it might be the case with Fichte also) as the machinery of the dialectical method, with its thesis, antithesis, and synthesis, carries him round and round from term to term of thought — like the Logos and the Spirit, which blow us whitherso ever they list — begins to suffer from dizziness at the apprehension that he has been the victim of phantasma goria and has not really moved at all. It is only later — if ever — that he recognises that the scene, though similar, is yet not altogether the same. It is only later — if ever — that he understands that the path of philosophy is no wandering from land to land more remote in search of a lost Absolute, a vanished God ; no setting forth of new and strange facts, of new Gods, but the revelation in fuller and fuller truth of the immanent reality in whom we live, and move, and have our being, — the manifestation in more closely-knit unity and more amply-detailed significance of that Infinite and Eternal, which was always present among us, though we saw but few, perhaps even no, traces of its power and glory. I.] THINKING IN VACUO. 7 To read Hegel often reminds us of the process we have to go through in trying to answer a riddle. The terms of the problem to be solved are all given to us : the features of the object are, it may be, fully described: and yet somehow we cannot at once tell what it is all about, or add up the sum of which we have the several items. We are waiting to learn the subject of the pro position, of which all these statements may be regarded as the predicates. Something, we feel, has undoubtedly been said : but we are at a loss to see what it has been said about. Our mind wanders round from one familiar object to another, and tries them in succession to see whether any one satisfies the several points in the statement and includes them all. We grope here and there for something we are acquainted with, in which the bits of the description may cohere, and get a unity which they cannot give themselves. When once we have hit upon the right object, our troubles are at an end : and the empty medium is now peopled with a creature of our imagination. We have reached a fixed point in the range of our conception, around which the given features may cluster. All this trouble caused by the Hegelian theory of what philosophy involves — viz. really beginning at the beginning, is saved by a device well known to the several branches of Science. It is the way with them to assume that the student has a rough general image of the objects which they examine; and under the guidance, or with the help of this generalised image, they go on to explain and describe its outlines more completely. They start with an approximate concep tion, such as anybody may be supposed to have ; and this they seek to render more definite. The geologist, for example, could scarcely teach geology, unless he could pre-suppose or produce some acquaintance on the 8 PROLEGOMENA. [l. part of his pupils with what Hume would have called an 'impression' or an 'idea' of the rocks and forma tions of which he has to treat. The geometer gives a short, and, as it were, popular explanation of the sense in which angles, circles, triangles, &c. are to be under stood : and then by the aid of these provisional defini tions we come to a more scientific notion of the same terms. The third book of Euclid, for example, brings before us a clearer notion of what a circle is, than the nominal explanation in the list of definitions. By means of these temporary aids, or, as we may call them, leading-strings for the intellect, the progress of the ordinary scientific student is made tolerably easy. But in philosophy, as it is found in Hegel, there is quite another way of working. The helps in question are absent : and until it be seen that they are not even needed, the Hegelian theory will remain a sealed mystery. For that which the first glance seemed to show as an enigma, is only the plain and unambiguous statement of thought. Instead of casting around for images and accustomed names, we have only to accept the several terms and articles in the development of thought as they present themselves. These terms merely require to be apprehended. They stand in no immediate need of illustration from our experience. What we have to bring to the work, is patience, self- restraint, the sacrifice of our cherished habits of mind, the surrender of the natural wish to see at once what it all comes to, what it is good for, how it squares with other convictions. As Bacon reminded his age, Into the kingdom of philosophy, as into the kingdom of heaven, none can enter, nisi sub persona infantis : i. e. unless he at least steadfastly resolve to renounce that world which lieth in the Evil. Ordinary knowledge consists in referring a new object I.] WHAT'S IN A NAME? 9 to a class of objects, that is to say, to a generalised image with which we are already acquainted. It is not so much cognition as re-cognition. ' " What is the truth ? " ' asked Lady Chettam of Mrs. Cadwallader in Middle- march. '"The truth? he is as bad as the wrong physic— nasty to take, and sure to disagree." " There could not be anything worse than that," said Lady Chettam, with so vivid a conception of the physic that she seemed to have learned something exact about Mr. Casaubon's disadvantages/ Once we have referred the new individual to a familiar category or a convenient metaphor, once we have given it a name, and introduced it into the society of our mental drawing-room, we are satisfied. We have put a fresh object in its appropriate drawer in the cabinet of our ideas : and hence, with the pride of a collector, we can calmly call it our own. But such acquaintance, proceeding from a mingling of memory and naming, is not the same thing as know ledge in the strict sense of the term \ ' What is he ? Do you know him ? * These are our questions : and we are satisfied when we learn his name and his calling. We may never have penetrated into the inner nature of those objects, with whose tout ensemble, or rough out lines, we are so much at home, that we fancy ourselves thoroughly cognisant of them. Classifications are only the first steps in science: and we do not understand a thought because we can view it under the guise of some of its illustrations. In the case of the English reader of Hegel some peculiar hindrances spring from the foreign language. In strong contrast to most of the well-known German philosophers, he may be said to write in the popular and national dialect of his country. Of course there ' Das Bekannte uberhaupt ist darum, well es bekannt ist, nicht erkannt.' Phenomenologie des Geistes, p. 24. IO PROLEGOMENA. [l. are tones and shades of meaning given to his words by the general context of his system. But upon the whole he did what he promised to J. H. Voss— the translator of Homer, and the poet of the Luise, in a letter written from Jena in 1805. He there says of his projects : 4 Luther has made the Bible, and you have made Homer speak German. No greater gift than this could be given to the nation. So long as a nation is not acquainted with a noble work in its own language, it is still barbarian, and does not regard the work as its own. Forget these two examples, and I may describe my own efforts as an attempt to teach philosophy to speak in German V Yet, in this matter of nationalising or Germanising philosophy, he only carried a step further what Wolff and even Kant had begun ; just as, on the other hand, he falls a long way short of what K. C. F. Krause, his contemporary, attempted in the same direction. Such an attempt, by its very nature, could never command a popular success. It runs directly counter to that tendency already noted, to escape the requirement to think and think for ourselves, by taking refuge under the shadow of a familiar term, which conceals in its apparent simplicity a great complex of ill-apprehended elements. The ordinary mind— and the more readily perhaps the more vulgar it is — flees for ease and safety to a cosmopolitan term, to the denationalised vocable of learned origin, to the language of general European culture. To such an ordinary mind — and up at least to a certain extent we all at times come under that heading — the effort to remain in the pellucid air of our unadulterated mother-tongue is too embarrassing to be long continued. Nor, after all, is it more than partially practicable. The well of German undefiled is apt to 1 Vermischte Schriften, vol. ii. p. 474. I.] THE RIGHTS OF COMMON SPEECH. 1 1 run dry. Hegel himself never shrinks when it is needful to appropriate non-Teutonic words, and is in the habit of employing the synonymous terms of native and of classical origin with a systematic difference of meaning l. Hegel is unquestionably par excellence the philosopher of Germany, — German through and through. For philosophy, though the common birthright of full-grown reason in all ages and countries, must like other universal and cosmopolitan interests, such as the State, the Arts, or the Church, submit to the limits and peculiarities imposed upon it by the natural divisions of race and language. The subtler nuances, as well as the coarser differences of national speech, make themselves vividly felt in the systems of philosophy, and defy translation. If Greek philosophy cannot, no more can German philosophy be turned into a body of English thought by a stroke of the translator's pen. There is a difference in this matter, a difference at least in degree, between the special sciences and philosophy. The several sciences have a de-nationalised and cosmo politan character, like the trades and industries of various nations ; they are pretty much the same in one country and another, especially when we consider the details, and neglect the general subdivisions. But in the political body, in the works of high art, and in the 1 e. g. Dasein and Existenz : Wirklichkeit and Realitcit : Wesen and Substanz. It is the same habit of curiously pondering over the tones and shades of language which leads him to something very like playing on words, and to etymologising, as one may call it, on un- etymological principles : e. g. the play on Mein and Meinung (vol. ii. 32 : cf. Werke, ii. 75) : the literal rendering of Erinnerung (Encycl. §§ 234 and 450); and the abrupt transitions, as it would seem, from literal to figurative use of such a term as Grund. At the same time it is well not to be prosaically certain that a free play of thought does not follow the apparently fortuitous assonance of words. 12 PROLEGOMENA. [l. systems of philosophy, the whole of the character and temperament of the several peoples finds its expression, and stands distinctly marked, in a shape of its own. If the form of German polity be not transferable to this side of the Channel, no more will German philosophy. Direct utilisation for English purposes is out of the question : the circumstances are too different. But the study of the great works of foreign thought is not on that account useless, any more than the study of the great works of foreign statesmanship. Hegel did good service, at least, by freeing philosophy from that aspect of an imported luxury, which it usually had, — as if it were an exotic plant removed from the bright air of Greece into the melancholy mists of Western Europe. ' We have still/ he says, ' to break down the partition between the language of philosophy, and that of ordinary consciousness : we have to over come the reluctance against thinking what we are familiar with1.' Philosophy must be brought face to face with ordinary life, so as to draw its strength from the actual and living present, and not from the memories or traditions of the past. It has to become the organised and completed thinking of what is contained blindly and vaguely in the various levels of popular intelligence, as these are more or less educated and ordered. It must grow naturally, as in ancient Greece, from the neces sities of the social situation, and not be a product of artificial introduction and nurture : the revelation by the mind's own energy of an implicit truth, not the com munication of a mystery sacramentally received. To suppose that a mere change of words can give this grace, would be absurd. Yet where the national life pulses strong, as that of Germany in those days did at first in letters and then in social reform, the dominant 1 Hegel's Leben (Rosenkranz), p. 552. I.] THE RIGHTS OF COMMON SPEECH. 13 note will make itself felt even in the neutral regions of speculation. It was a step on the right road to banish a pompous and aristocratic dialect from philosophy, and to lead it back to those words and forms of speech, which are at least in silent harmony with the national feeling. CHAPTER II. WHY TRANSLATE HEGEL? ' BUT/ it is urged, ' though it be well to let the stream of foreign thought irrigate some of our philosophical pastures, though we should not for ever entrench our selves in our insularity — why try to introduce Hegel, of all philosophers confessedly the most obscure? Why not be content with the study and the " exploitation " of Kant, whom Germans themselves still think so impor tant as to expound him with endless comment and criticism, and who has at length found, after some skirmishes, a recognised place in the English philo sophical curriculum ? Why seek for more Teutonic thinking that can be found in Schopenhauer, and found there in a clear and noble style, luminous in the highest degree, and touching with no merely academic abstruse- ness the problems of life and death ? Or — as that song is sweetest to men which is the newest to ring in their ears — why not render accessible to English readers the numerous and suggestive works of Eduard von Hart- mann, and of Friedrich Nietzsche — not to mention Robert Hamerling 1 ? Or, finally, why not give us more and ever more translations of the works in logic, ethics, psychology, or metaphysics, of those many admirable teachers in the German universities, whom it would be 1 A book by V. Knauer published last year (Hauptprobleme der Philosophic), a series of popular lectures, gives one-sixth of its space to the 'Atomistic of Will' by the Austrian poet Hamerling. PR 0 TES T A GAINST HEGELIANISM. 1 5 invidious to try to single out by name ? As for Hegel, his system, in the native land of the philosopher, is utterly discredited ; its influence is extinct ; it is dead as a door-nail. It is a pity to waste labour and distract attention, and that in English lands, where there are plenty of problems of our own to solve, by an attempt, which must perforce be futile, to resuscitate these defunctitudes ? ' That Hegelianism has been utterly discredited, in certain quarters, is no discovery reserved for these later days. But on this matter perhaps we may borrow an analogy. If the reader will be at the trouble to take up two English newspapers of opposite partisanship and compare the reports from their foreign correspondents on some question of home politics, he may, if a novice, be surprised to learn that according to one, the opinion e. g. of Vienna is wholly adverse to the measure, while, according to the other, that opinion entirely approves. It is no new thing to find Hegelianism in general obloquy. Even in 1830 the Catholic philosopher and theologian Giinther1— an admirer, but by no means a follower of Hegel — wrote that, ' for some years it had been the fashion in learned Germany to look upon philosophy, and above all Hegelian philosophy, as a door-mat on which everybody cleaned his muddy boots before entering the sanctuary of politics and religion/ What is true as regards the alleged surcease of Hegelianism is that in the reaction which from various causes turned itself against philosophy in the two decennia after 1848, that system, as the most deeply committed part of the 'metaphysical* host, suffered most severely. History and science seemed to triumph along the whole line. But it may be perhaps permissible to remark that Hegelianism had predicted 1 Hegel's Briefe, ii. 349. 1 6 PROLEGOMENA. [li. for itself the fate that it proved had fallen on all other philosophies. After the age of Idealism comes the turn of Realism. The Idea had to die— had to sink as a germ in the fields of nature and history before it could bear its fruit. Above all it is not to be expected that such a system, so ambitious in aim and concentrated in expression, could find immediate response and at once disclose all its meaning. His first disciples are not the truest interpreters of any great teacher. What he saw in the one comprehensive glance of genius, his successors must often be content to gather by the slow accumulation of years, and perhaps centuries, of experience. It is not to Theophrastus that we go for the truest and fullest con ception of Aristotelianism ; nor is Plato to be measured by what his immediate successors in the Academy managed to make out of him. It is now more than a century since Kant gave his lesson to the public, and we are still trying to get him focussed in a single view : it may be even longer till Hegel comes fully within the range of our historians of thought. Aristotelianism too had to wait centuries till it fully entered the conscious ness even of the thinking world. It is to be said too that without Hegel it would be diffi cult to imagine what even teachers, like Lotze, who were very unlike him, would have had to say. It does not need a very wide soul, nor need one be a mere dilet- tantist eclectic, to find much of Schopenhauer's work far from incompatible with his great, and as some have said, complementary opposite. It is not indeed prudent as yet for a writer in Germany who wishes to catch the general ear to affix too openly a profession of Hegelian principles, and he will do well to ward off suspicion by some disparaging remarks on the fantastic methods, the overfondness for system, the contempt for common sense and scientific results which, as he declares, vitiate all II.] COUNTER-PROTEST FOR HEGELIANISM. 17 the speculations of the period from 1794 to 1830. But under the names of Spinoza and of Leibniz the leaven of Hegelian principles has been at work : and if the Philistines solve the riddle of the intellectual Samson, it is because they have ploughed with his heifer, — because his ideas are part of the modern stock of thought,— not from what they literally read in the great thinkers at the close of the seventeenth century. Last year saw appear in Germany two excellent treatises describable as popular introductions to philosophy \ one by a thinker who has never disguised his obligations to Hegel, the other by a teacher in the University of Berlin who may in many ways be considered as essentially kindred with our general English style of thought. But both treatises are more allied in character to the spirit of the Hegelian attempts to comprehend man and God than to the forma- listic and philological disquisitions which have for some years formed the staple of German professorial activity. And, lastly, the vigorous thinker, who a quarter of a century ago startled the reading public by the portent of a new metaphysic which should be the synthesis of Schelling and Schopenhauer, has lately informed us2 that 'his affinity to Hegel is, taken all in all, greater than his affinity to any other philosopher'; and that that affinity extends to all that in Hegel has essential and permanent value. But it is not on Eduard von Hartmann's commenda tion that we need rest our estimate of Hegelianism. We shall rather say that, till more of Hegel has been assimi lated, he must still block the way. Things have altered greatly in the last twenty years, it is true ; and ideas of 1 J. Volkelt, Vortrdge ziir Einfithrung in die Philosophic der Gegen- wart (Munchen 1892) : F. Paulsen, Einleitung in die Philosophic (Berlin 1892). K. v. Hartmann, Kritische Wanderungen, p. 74. C 1 8 PROLEGOMENA. [11. more or less Hegelian origin have taken their place in the common stock of philosophic commodities. But it will probably be admitted by those best qualified to speak on the subject, that the shower has not as yet penetrated very deeply into the case-hardened soil, still less saturated it in the measure most likely to cause fruitful shoots to grow forth. We have to go back to Hegel in the same spirit as we go to Kant, and, for that matter, to Plato or Descartes : or, as the moderns may go back — to borrow from another sphere — to Dante or Shakespeare. We do not want the modern poet to resuscitate the style and matter of King Lear or of the Inferno. Yet as the Greek tragedian steeped his soul in the language and the legend of Homeric epic, as Dante nurtured his spirit on the noble melodies of Mantua's poet ; so philosophy, if it is to go forth strong and effective, must mould into its own substance the living thought of former times. It would be as absurd, and as impossible to be literally and simply a Hegelian, — if that means one for whom Hegel sums up all philo sophy and all truth — as it is to be at the present day in the literal sense a Platonist or an Aristotelian. The world may be slow, the world of opinion and thought may linger : e pur si muove. We too have our own problems —the same, no doubt, in a sense, from age to age, and yet infinitely varying and never in two ages alike. New stars have appeared on the spiritual sky ; and whether they have in them the eternal light or only the flash and glare of a passing meteor, they alter the aspects of the night in which we are still waiting for the dawn. A new language, born of new relations of ideas, or of new ideas, is perforce for our generation the vehicle of all utterances, and we cannot again speak the dialect, however imposing or however quaint, of a vanished day. II.] COUNTER-PROTEST FOR HEGELIAN1SM. 19 And for that reason there must always be a new philosophy, couched in the language of the age, sym pathetic with its hopes and fears, conscious of its beliefs, more or less sensible of its problems — as indeed we may be confident there always will be. But, per haps, the warrior in that battle against illusion and pre judice, against the sloth which takes things as they are and the poorness of spirit which is satisfied with first appearances, will not do wisely to disdain the past. He will not indeed equip himself with rusty swords and clumsy artillery from the old arsenals. But he will not disdain the lessons of the past, — its methods and princi ples of tactics and strategy. Recognising perhaps some defects and inequalities in the methods and aims of thought most familiar to him and current in his vicinity, he may go abroad for other samples, even though they be not in all respects worth his adoption. And so without taking Hegel as omniscient, or pledging him self to every word of the master, he may think from his own experience that there is much in the system that will be helpful, when duly estimated and assimi lated, to others. There is — and few can be so bigoted or so positive-minded as to regret it — there is un questionably a growing interest in English-speaking countries in what may be roughly called philosophy — the attempt, unprejudiced by political, scientific, or ecclesiastical dogma, to solve the questions as to what the world really is, and what man's place and func tion is. ' The burthen of the mystery, the heavy and the weary weight of all this unintelligible world ' is felt — felt widely and sometimes felt deeply. To the direct lightening of that burthen and that mystery it is the privilege of our profoundest thinkers and our far-seeing poets and artists to contribute. To the translator of Hegel there falls the humbler task of c 2 20 PROLEGOMENA. making accessible, if it may be, something of one of the later attempts at a solution of the enigma of life and existence,— an attempt which for a time dazzled some of the keenest intellects of its age, and which has at least impressed many others with the conviction, born of momentary flashes from it of vast illuminant power, that — si sic otnnia— there was here concealed a key to many puzzles, and a guard against many illusions likely to beset the inquirer after truth. CHAPTER III. ENGLISH PHILOSOPHY AND HEGEL. ALTHOUGH we need not take too seriously Hegel's remark (vol. ii. p. 13) on the English conception of philo sophy, it may be admitted that, by the dominant school of English thought, philosophy, taken in the wide sense it has predominantly born abroad, was, not so very long ago, all but entirely ignored. Causes of various kinds had turned the energy of the English mind into other directions, not less essential to the common welfare. Practical needs and an established social system helped to bind down studies to definite and particular objects, and to exclude what seemed vague and general investi gations with no immediate bearing on the business of life. Hence philosophy in England could hardly exist except when it was reduced to the level of a special branch of science, or when it could be used as a recep tacle for the principles and methods common to all the sciences. The general term was often used to denote the wisdom of this world, or the practical exhibition of self-control in life and action. For those researches, which are directed to the objects once considered proper to philosophy, the more definite and characteristic term came to be Mental and Moral Science. The old name was in certain circles restricted to denote the vague and irregular speculations of those thinkers, who either lived before the rise of exact science, or who acted in defiance of its precepts and its example. One large and influential class of English 22 PROLEGOMENA. [ill. thinkers inclined to sweep philosophy altogether away, as equivalent to metaphysics and obsolete forms of error ; and upon the empty site thus obtained they sought to construct a psychological theory of mind, or they tried to arrange and codify those general remarks upon the general procedure of the sciences which are known under the name of Inductive Logic. A smaller, but not less vigorous, school of philosophy looked upon their business as an extension and rounding off of science into a complete unification of knowledge. The first is illustrated by the names of J. S. Mill and Mr. Bain : the second is the doctrine of Mr. Herbert Spencer. The encyclopaedic aggregate of biological, psycho logical, ethical and social investigation which Mr. Spencer pursues, under the general guidance of the formula of evolution by differentiation and integration, still pro ceeds on its course : but though its popularity — as such popularity goes — is vast and more than national, it does not and probably cannot find many imitators. Very differently stand matters with the movement in psycho logy and logic. Here the initiative has led to divergent and unexpected developments. Psychology, which at first was partly an ampler and a more progressive logic, a theory of the origin and nature of knowledge, partly a propaedeutic to the more technical logic and ethics, and pursued in a loosely introspective way, has gravi tated more and more towards its experimental and phy siological side, with occasional velleities to assume the abstractly-mathematical character of a psycho-physical science. Logic, on the other hand, has also changed its scope. Not content to be a mere tool of the sciences or a mere criterion for the estimation of evidence, it has in one direction grown into a systematic effort to become an epistemology — a system of the first principles of knowledge and reality — a metaphysic of science ; and III.] PHASES OF CONTEMPORARY THOUGHT. 23 in another it has sought to realise the meaning of those old forms of inference which the logicians of half a cen tury ago were inclined to pooh-pooh as obsolete. Most remarkable — and most novel of all — is the vast increase of interest and research in the problems of ethics and of what is called the philosophy of religion — subjects which at that date were literally burning questions, apt to scorch the fingers of those who touched them. In all of this, but especially marked in some leading thinkers, the ruling feature is the critical — the sceptical, i. e. the eager, watchful, but self-restrained — attitude towards its themes. Ever driving on to find a deeper unity than shows on the surface, and to get at principles, the modern thinker— and in this we see the permanent and almost overwhelming influence of Kant upon him — recoils from the dogmatism of system, at the very moment it seems to be within his grasp. Thus the recent products of English thought have been, as Mr. Spencer has taught us to say, partly in the line of differentiation, partly of integration. At one moment it seems as if the ancient queen of the sciences sat like Hecuba, exul, mops, while her younger daughters enjoyed the freedom and progress of specialisation. The wood seems lost behind the trees. And at another, again, the centripetal force seems to preponderate : every department, logic, ethics, psychology, sociology, rapidly carries its students on and up to fundamental questions, if not to fundamental principles. Philo sophy — the one and undivided truth and quest of truth — emerges fresh, vigorous, and as yet rather indeter minate, from the mass of detailed investigations. That the position is now altered from what it was in times when knowledge had fewer departments, is obvious. The task of the ' synoptic ' mind— which Plato claims for the philosopher— grows increasingly difficult : but 24 PROLEGOMENA. [ill. that is hardly a reason for performing it in a more perfunctory way. It seems rather as if in such a crisis one of the great reconstructive systems of a preceding age might be in some measure helpful. If we consult history, it is at once clear that philosophy, or the pursuit of ultimate reality and permanent truth, went hand in hand with scientific researches into facts and their particular explanations. In their earlier stages the two tendencies of thought were scarcely distinguishable. The philosophers of Ionia and Magna Graecia were also the scientific pioneers of their time. Their fragmentary remains remind us at times of the modern theories of geology and biology, — at other times of the teachings of idealism. The same thing is comparatively true of the earlier philosophers of Modern Europe. The seventeenth and eighteenth centuries, in spite of Bacon and Newton, endeavoured to study the mental and moral life by a method which was a strange mixture of empiricism and metaphysics. In words, indeed, the thinkers from Descartes to Wolff duly emphasise, perhaps over-emphasise, the antithesis between the extended and the intellectual. But in practice their course is not so clear. Their mental philosophy is often only a preliminary medicina mentis to set the individual mind in good order for undertaking the various tasks awaiting a special research. They are really eager to get on to business, and only, as it were, with regret spend time in this clearance of mental faculty. And when they do deal with objects, the material and extended tends to become the dominant conception, the basis of reality. The human mind, that nobilissima substantia, is treated only as an aggregate, or a receptacle, of ideas, and the mens, — with them all nearly as with Spinoza, — is only an idea carport's, and that phrase not taken so III.] THE EMANCIPATION OF PHILOSOPHY. 25 highly as Spinoza's perhaps should be taken. In the works of these thinkers, as of the pre-Socratics, there is one element which may be styled philosophical, and another element which maybe styled scientific, — if we use both words vaguely. But with Socrates in the ancient, and with Kant in the modern epoch of philo sophy, an attempt was made to get the boundary between the two regions definitively drawn. The dis tinction was in the first place accompanied by something like turning the back upon science and popular concep tions. Socrates withdrew thought from disquisitions concerning the nature of all things, and fixed it upon man and the state of man. Kant left the broad fields of actually-attained knowledge, and inquired into the central principle on which the acquisition of science, the laws of human life, and the ideals of art and religion, were founded. The change thus begun was not unlike that which Copernicus effected in the theory of Astronomy. Hu man personality, either in the actualised forms of the State, or in the abstract shape of the Reason, — that intellectual liberty, which is a man's true world,— was, at least by implication, made the pivot around which the system of the sciences might turn. In the contest, which according to Reid prevails between Common Sense and Philosophy, the presumptions of the former have been distinctly reversed, and Kant, like Socrates, has shown that it is not the several items of fact, but the humanity, the moral law, the thought, which under lies these doctrines, which give the real resting-point and true centre of movement. But this negative atti tude of philosophy to the sciences is only the beginning, needed to secure a standing-ground. In the ancient world Aristotle, and in the modern Hegel (as the inheritor of the labours of Fichte and Schelling), exhibit 26 PROLEGOMENA. [ill. the movement outwards to reconquer the universe, pro ceeding from that principle which Socrates and Kant had emphasised in its fundamental worth. Mr. Mill, in the closing chapter of his Logic, has briefly sketched the ideal of a science to which he gives the name of Teleology, corresponding in the ethical and practical sphere to a Philosophia Prima, or Meta physics, in the theoretical. This ideal and ultimate court of appeal is to be valid in Morality, and also in Prudence, Policy and Taste. But the conception, although a desirable one, falls short of the work which Hegel assigns to philosophy. What he intended to accomplish with detail and regular evolution was not a system of principles in these departments of action only, but a theory which would give its proper place in our total Idea of reality to Art, Science, and Religion, to all the consciousness of ordinary life, and to the evolution of the physical universe. Philosophy ranges over the whole field of actuality, or existing fact. Abstract prin ciples are all very well in their way ; but they are not philosophy. If the world in its historical and its present life develops into endless detail in regular lines, philo sophy must equally develop the narrowness of its first principles into the plenitude of a System, — into what Hegel calls the Idea. His point of view may be gathered from the following remarks in a review of Hamann, an erratic friend and fellow-citizen of Kant's. ' Hamann would not put himself to the trouble, which in an higher sense God undertook. The ancient philo sophers have described God under the image of a round ball. But if that be His nature, God has unfolded it ; and in the actual world He has opened the closed shell of truth into a system of Nature, into a State-system, a system of Law and Morality, into the system of the world's History. The shut fist has become an open ill.] THE WORK OF PHILOSOPHY. 27 hand, the fingers of which reach out to lay hold of man's mind, and draw it to Himself. Nor is the human mind a self-involved intelligence, blindly moving within its own secret recesses. It is no mere feeling and groping about in a vacuum, but an intelligent system of rational organisation. Of that system Thought is the summit in point of form : and Thought may be described as the capability of going beyond the mere surface of God's self-expansion, — or rather as the capability, by means of reflection upon it, of entering into it, and then when the entrance has been secured, of retracing in thought God's expansion of Himself. To take this trouble is the express duty and end of ends set before the thinking mind, ever since God laid aside His rolled-up form, and revealed Himself1.' Enthusiastic admirers have often spoken as if the salvation of the time could only come from the He gelian philosophy. 'Grasp the secret of Hegel,' they say, 'and you will find a cure for the delusions of your own mind, and the remedy which will set right the wrongs of the world.' These high claims to be a panacea were never made by Hegel himself. According to him, as according to Aristotle, philosophy as such can pro duce nothing new. Practical statesmen, and theoretical reformers, may do their best to correct the inequalities of their time. But the very terms in which Bacon scornfully depreciated one great concept of philosophy are to be accepted in their literal truth. Like a virgin consecrated to God, she bears no fruit2. She repre sents the spirit of the world, resting, as it were, when one step in the progress has been accomplished, and surveying the advance which has been made. ' Philo sophy is not,' says Fichte, ' even a means to shape life : 1 Vermischte Schriften, vol. ii. p. 87. 2 De Augnt. Scient. iii. 5. 28 PROLEGOMENA. [in. for it lies in a totally different world, and what is to have an influence upon life must itself have sprung from life. Philosophy is only a means to the knowledge of life.' Nor has it the vocation to edify men, and take the place of religion on the higher levels of intellect. 'The philosopher/ Fichte boldly continues, 'has no God at all and can have no God : he has only a con cept of the concept or of the Idea of God. It is only in life that there is God and religion : but the philosopher as such is not the whole complete man, and it is impos sible for any one to be only a philosopher V Philosophy does not profess to bring into being what ought to be, but is not yet. It sets up no mere ideals, which must wait for some future day in order to be realised. Enough for it if it show what the world ts, if it were what it professes to be, and what in a way it must be, otherwise it could not be even what it is. The subject- matter of philosophy is that which is always realising and always realised — the world in its wholeness as it is and has been. It seeks to put before us, and embody in permanent outlines, the universal law of spiritual life and growth, and not the local, temporary, and indi vidual acts of human will. Those who ask philosophy to construe, or to deduce a priori a single blade of grass, or a single act of a man, must not be grieved if their request sounds absurd and meets with no answer. The sphere of philosophy is the Universal. We may say, if we like, that it is retrospective. It is the spectator of all time and all existence : it is its duty to view things sub specie aeter- nitatis. To comprehend the universe of thought in all its formations and all its features, to reduce the solid structures, which mind has created, to fluidity and 1 The passages occur in some notes (written down by F. in reference to the charge of Atheism) published in his Werke, v. pp. 342, 348. ill.] THE WORK OF PHILOSOPHY. 29 transparency in the pure medium of thought, to set free the fossilised intelligence which the great magician who wields the destinies of the world has hidden under the mask of Nature, of the Mind of man, of the works of Art, of the institutions of the State and the orders of Society, and of religious forms and creeds : — such is the complicated problem of philosophy. Its special work is to comprehend the world, not try to make it better. If it were the purpose of philosophy to reform and im prove the existing state of things, it comes a little too late for such a task. 'As the thought of the world/ says Hegel, 'it makes its first appearance at a time, when the actual fact has consummated its process of formation, and is now fully matured. This is the doctrine set forth by the notion of philosophy; but it is also the teaching of history. It is only when the actual world has reached its full fruition that the ideal rises to confront the reality, and builds up, in the shape of an intellectual realm, that same world grasped in its substantial being. When philosophy paints its grey in grey, some one shape of life has meanwhile grown old : and grey in grey, though it brings it into knowledge, cannot make it young again. The owl of Minerva does not start upon its flight, until the evening twilight has begun to fall V 1 Philosophic des Rechts, p. 20 (Werke, viii). CHAPTER IV. HEGEL AND THEOLOGY. EVEN an incidental glance into Hegel's Logic can not fail to discover the frequent recurrence of the name of God, and the discussion of matters not gene rally touched upon; unless in works bearing upon religion. There were two questions which seem to have had a certain fascination for Hegel. One of them, a rather unpromising problem, referred to the distances between the several planets in the solar system, and the law regulating these intervals1. The other and more intimate problem turned upon the value of the proofs usually offered in support of the being of God. That God is the supreme certitude of the mind, the basis of all reality and knowledge, is what Hegel no more put in question, than did Descartes, Spinoza, or Locke. What he often repeated was that the matter in these proofs must be distinguished from the imperfect manner in which the arguers presented it. Again and again 1 Hegel's Leben, p. 155. It was in his dissertation de Orbitis Planetarum, that the notorious contretemps occurred, whereby, whilst the philosopher, leaning to a Pythagorean proportion, hinted — in a line — that it was unnecessary to expect a planet between Mars and Jupiter, astronomers in the same year discovered Ceres, the first-detected of the Planetoids. A good deal has been made out of this trifle ; but it has not yet been shown that the corroboration was anything but the luck of the other hypothesis. PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION. 31 in his Logic, as well as in other discussions more especially devoted to it, he examines this problem. His persistence in this direction might earn for him that title of 'Knight of the Holy Ghost/ by which Heine, in one of the delightful poems of his ' Reise- bilder,' describes himself to the maid of Klausthal in the Harz. The poet of Love and of Freedom had undoubted rights to rank among the sacred band : but so also had the philosopher. Like the Socrates whom Plato describes to us, he seems to feel that he has been commissioned to reveal the truth of God, and quicken men by an insight into the right wisdom. Nowhere in the modern period of philosophy has higher spirit breathed in the utterances of a thinker. The same theme is claimed as the common heritage of philosophy and religion. A letter to Duboc1, the father of a modern German novelist, lets us see how important this aspect of his system was to Hegel himself. He had been asked to give a succinct ex planation of his standing-ground : and his answer begins by pointing out that philosophy seeks to ap prehend in reasoned knowledge the same truth which the religious mind has in its faith. Words like these may at first sight suggest the bold soaring of ancient speculation in the times of Plato and Aristotle, or even the theories of the medieval School men. They sound as if he proposed to do for the modern world, and in the full light of modern know ledge, what the Schoolmen tried to accomplish within the somewhat narrow conceptions of medieval Chris tianity and Greek logic. Still there is a difference between the two cases. While the Doctors of the Vermischte Schriften, vol. ii. p. 520. Duboc was a retired hatter, of French origin, who had settled at Hamburg (Hegel's Briefe. ii. 76 seqq.). 32 PROLEGOMENA. [iv. Church, in appearance at least, derived the form of exposition, and the matter of their systems, from two independent and apparently heterogeneous sources, the modern Scholastic of Hegel claims to be a har monious unity, body finding soul, and soul giving itself body. And while the Hegelian system has the all-embracing and encyclopaedic character by which Scholastic science threw its arms around heaven and earth, it has also the untrammeled liberty of the Greek thinkers. Hegel, in short, shows the union of these two modes of speculation : free as the ancient, and compre hensive as the modern. His theory is the explication of God ; but of God in the actuality and plenitude of the world, and not as a transcendent Being, such as an over-reverent philosophy has sometimes supposed him, in the solitude of a world beyond. The greatness of a philosophy is its power of com prehending facts. The most characteristic fact of modern times is Christianity. The general thought and action of the civilised world has been alternately fascinated and repelled, but always influenced, and to a high degree permeated, by the Christian theory of life, and still more by the faithful vision of that life displayed in the Son of Man. To pass that great cloud of witness and leave it on the other side, is to admit that your system is no key to the secret of the world, — even if we add, as some will prefer, of the world as it is and has been. And therefore the Hegelian system, if it is to be a philosophy at all, must be in this sense Christian. But it is neither a critic, nor an apologist of historical Christianity. The voice of philosophy is as that of the Jewish doctor of the Law : ' If this council or this work be of men, it will come to nought : but if it be of God, ye cannot overthrow it.' Philosophy examines what is, and not IV.] HEGEL AND CHRISTIANITY. 33 what, according to some opinions, ought to be. Such a point of view requires no discussion of the 'How' or the 'Why' of Christianity. It involves no inquiry into historical documents, or into the belief in miracles : for to it Christianity rests only incidentally on the evidence of history; and miracles, as vulgarly explained, can find no reception in a philosophical system. For it Christianity is ' absolute religion ' : religion i. e. which has fully become and realised all that religion meant to be. That religion has, of course, its historical side : it appeared at a definite epoch in the annals of our race : it revealed itself in a unique personality in a remarkable nation. And at an early period of his life Hegel had tried to gather up in one conception the traits of that august figure, in his life and speech and death. But, in the light of philosophy, this historical side shrivels up as comparatively unimportant. Not the personality, but the ' revelation of reason ' through man's spirit : not the annals of a life once spent in serving God and men, but the words of the ' Eternal Gospel,' are hence forth the essence of Christianity. Thus the controlling and central conception of life and actuality, which is the final explanation of all that man thinks and does, has a twofold aspect. There is, as it were, a double Absolute — for under this name philosophy has what in religion corresponds to God. It is true that in the final form of his system the Absolute Spirit has three phases — each as it were passing on into and incorporated with the next — Art working out its implications till it appears as Religion, and Religion calling for its perfection in Philosophy. But in the Phenomenology, his first work, the religion of Art only intervenes as a grade from ' natural ' religion to religion manifest or revealed ; and in the first edition of the Encyclopaedia what is subsequently called Art is 34 PROLEGOMENA. [iv. entitled the Religion of Art. It is in entire accord ance with these indications when in the Lectures on Aesthetics1 it is said 'the true and original position of Art is to fee the first-come immediate self-satisfaction of Absolute Spirit ' ; though in our days (it is added) ' its form has ceased to be the highest need of the spirit/ It is hardly too much then to say that, for Hegel, the Absolute has two phases, Religion and Philosophy. The Hegelian view presents itself most decisively, though perhaps with a little lecture-like over-insistance, in the Philosophy of Religion 2. ' The object of religion as of philosophy is the eternal truth in its very objec tivity—God and nothing but God,— and the "explica tion" of God. Philosophy is not a wisdom of the world, but cognition of the non-worldly : not a cogni tion of the external mass of empirical existence and life, but cognition of what is eternal, what is God, and what flows from His nature. For this nature must reveal and develop itself. Hence philosophy " explicates " itself only when it " explicates " religion ; and in explicating itself it explicates religion. . . . Thus religion and philosophy coincide : in fact, philosophy is itself a divine service, is a religion : for it is the same renunciation of subjective fancies and opinions, and is engaged with God alone/ Again, it may be asked in what sense philosophy has to deal with God and with Truth. These two terms are often synonyms in Hegel. All the objects of science, all the terms of thought, all the forms of reality, lead out of themselves, and seek for a centre and resting-point. They are severally inadequate and partial, and they crave adequacy and completeness. They tend to organise themselves ; to call out more 1 Werke, x. i, p. 131. 2 Werke, xi. p. 21. 35 IV.] PHILOSOPHY AND RELIGION. and more distinctly the fuller reality which they pre suppose, — which must have been, otherwise they could not have been : they reduce their first appearance of completeness to its due grade of inadequacy and bring out their complementary side, so as to constitute a system or universe; and in this tendency to a self- correcting unity consists their progress to truth. Their untruth lies in isolation and pretended independence or finality. This completed unity, in which all things receive their entireness and become adequate, is their Truth : and that Truth, as known in religious language, is God. Rightly or wrongly, God is thus interpreted in the Logic of Hegel. Such a position must seem very strange to one who is familiar only with the sober studies of English philosophy. In whatever else the leaders of the several schools in this country disagree, they are nearly all at one in banishing God and religion to a world beyond the present sublunary sphere, to an inscrutable region beyond the scope of scientific in quiry, where statements may be made at will, but where we have no power of verifying any statement whatever. This is the common doctrine of Spencer and Mansel, of Hamilton and Mill. Even those English thinkers, who show some anxiety to support what is at present called Theism, generally rest content with vindicating for the mind the vague perception of a Being beyond us, and differing from us incommen- surably. God is to them a residual phenomenon, a marginal existence. Outside the realm of experience and knowledge there is not-nothing— a something— beyond definite circumscription : incalculable, and therefore an object, possibly of fear, possibly of hope : the reflection in the utter darkness of a great What- may-it-not-be ? He is the Unknown Power, felt by D 2 36 PROLEGOMENA. what some of these writers call intuition, and others call experience. They do not however allow to know ledge any capacity of apprehending in detail the truths fhich belong to the kingdom of God. Now the whole aching of Hegel is the overthrow of the limits thus it to religious thought. To him all thought, and all actuality when it is grasped by knowledge, is from man's side, an exaltation of the mind towards God : while, when regarded from the divine standing-point, it is the manifestation by God of His own nature in its infinite variety. It is only when we fix our eyes clearly on these general features in his speculation, that we can under stand why he places the maturity of ancient philosophy in the time of Plotinus and Proclus. Not that these Neo-Platonists are, as thinkers, of power equal to their master of Athens. But, in the realm of the blind the one-eyed may be king. The later thinkers set their vision more distinctly and persistently on the land that is eternal — 'on the further side of being/ to quote Plato's phrase. It is for the same reason Hegel gives so much attention to the religious or semi-religious theories of Jacob Bohme and of Jacobi, though these men were in many ways so unlike himself. CHAPTER V. PSEUDO-IDEALISM I JACOBI. IT is hazardous to try to sum up the net result of a philosophy in a few paragraphs. Since Aristotle sepa rated the pure 'energy ' of philosophy from the activities which leave works made and deeds done behind them, it need scarcely be repeated that the result of a philo sophical system is nothing palpable or tangible,— nothing on which you can put your finger, and say definitely : Here it is. The spirit of a philosophy always refuses to be incarcerated in a formula, however deftly you may try to charm it there. The statement of the principle or tendency of a philosophical system tells not what that system is, but what it is not. It marks off the position from contiguous points of view ; and on that account never gets beyond the border-land, which separates that system from something else. The method and process of reasoning is as essential in knowledge, as the result to which it leads : and the method in this case is thoroughly bound up with the subject-matter. A mere analysis of the method, there fore, or a mere record of the purpose and outcome of the system, would be, the one as well as the other, a fruitless labour, and come to nothing but words. Thus any attempt to convey a glimpse of the truth in a few sentences and in large outlines seems foreclosed. 38 PROLEGOMENA. |_v- The theory of Hegel has an abhorrence of mere generalities, of abstractions with no life in them, and no growth out of them. His principle has to prove and verify itself to be true and adequate : and that verification fills up the whole circle of circles, of which philosophy is said to consist. It seems as if there were in Hegel two distinct habits of mind which the world — the outside observer — rarely sees except in separation. On one hand there is a sympathy with mystical and intuitional minds, with the upholders of immediate knowledge and of innate ideas, with those who find that science and demonstration rather tend to distract from the one thing needful — who would 'lie in Abraham's bosom all the year/ — those who would fain lay their grasp upon the whole before they have gone through the drudgery of details. On the other hand, there is within him a strongly ' rationalising ' and non-visionary intellect, with a prac tical and realistic bent, and the full scientific spirit. Schelling, in an angry mood, could describe him as 'the quintessence of all that is prosaic, both outside and in1.' Yet, seen from other points of view, Hegel has been accused of dreaminess, pietism, and mystical theology. His merging of the ordinary contrasts of thought in a completer truth, and what would popularly be described as his mixing up of religious with logical questions, and the general unfathomableness of his doctrine, — all seem to support such a charge. Yet all this is not incon sistent with a rough and incisive vigour of under standing, a plainness of reason, and a certain hardness of temperament. This philosopher is in many ways not distinguishable from the ordinary citizen, and there are not unfrequent moments when his wife hears him groan over the providence that condemned him to be a 1 Aus Schellings Leben (Plitt), ii. 161. V.] CONTRASTS IN HEGEL. 39 philosopher1. He is contemptuous towards all weakly sentimentalism, and almost brutal in his emphasis on the reasonableness of the actual and on the folly of dreaming the might-have-been ; and keeps his house hold accounts as carefully as the average head of a family. And, perhaps, this convergence of two ten dencies of thought may be noticed in the gradual maturing of his ideas. In the period of his ' Lehrjahre/ or apprenticeship, from 1793 to 1800, we can see the study of religion in the earlier part of that time at Bern succeeded by the study of politics and philo sophy at Frankfort-on-the-Main. His purpose on the whole may be termed an attempt to combine breadth with depth, the intensity of the mystic who craves for union with Truth, with the extended range and explicitness of those who multiply knowledge. ' The depth of the mind is only so deep as its courage to expand and lose itself in its explica tion V It must prove its profundity by the ordered fullness of the knowledge which it has realised. The position and the work of Hegel will not be intelligible unless we keep in view both of these antagonistic points. The purpose of philosophy — as has been pointed out — is, for Hegel — to know God, which is to know things in their Truth— to see all things in God— to comprehend the world in its eternal significance. Supposing the purpose capable of being achieved, what method is open to its attainment? There is on one hand the method of ordinary science in dealing with its objects. These are things, found as it were projected into space before the observer, lying outside one another in prima facie indepen- 1 Hegel's Brief e, ii. 377. 2 Phenomenologie des Geistes, p. 9. 40 PROLEGOMENA. [v. dence, though connected (by a further rinding) with each other by certain 'accidents' called qualities and relations. Among the objects of knowledge, there are included, by the somewhat naive intellect that accepts tradition like a physical fact; certain 'things* of a rather peculiar character. One of these is God : the others, which a historical criticism has subjoined, are the Soul and the World. And whatever may be said of the thinghood, reality, or existence of the World, there is no doubt that God and the Soul figure, and figure largely, in the consciousness of the human race as entities, differing probably in many respects from other things, but still possessed of certain fundamental features in common, and thus playing a part as distinct realities amongst other realities. Given such objects, it is natural for a reflecting mind to attempt to make out a science of God and a science of the Soul, just as of other 'things.* And to these a system-loving philosopher might add a science of the world (Cosmology)1. It was felt, indeed, that these objects were peculiar and unique. Thus, for example, as regards God, it was held necessary by the logician who saw tradition in its true light to prove His 'exist ence': and various arguments to that end were at different times devised. With regard to the human Soul, similarly, it was considered essential to establish its independent reality as a thing really separate from the bodily organism with which its phenomena were obviously connected, — to prove, in short, its substantial existence, and its emancipation from the bodily fate of dissolution and decay. With reference to the World, the problem was rather different : it was felt that the name suggested problems for thought rather than denoted 1 Cf. Notes and Illustrations in vol. ii. 396, and chapter iii. of the Logic. v-] KANT'S CRITICISMS. 41 reality. How can we predicate of the whole what is predicable of its parts? This or that may have a beginning and a cause, may have a limit and an end : but can the totality be presented under these aspects, without leading to self-contradiction ? And the result of these questions in the case of ' Cosmology * was to shed in the long run similar doubts on 'Rational* Theology and ' Rational * Psychology. Practically this metaphysical science— which is so called as dealing with a province or provinces of being beyond the ordinary or natural (physical) realities- treated God and the Soul by the same terms (or categories) as it used in dealing with ' material ' objects. God e. g. was a force, a cause, a being ; so, too, was the Soul. The main butt of Kant's destructive Criticism of pure Reason is to challenge the justice of including God and the Soul among the objects of science, among the things we can know as we may know plants or stars. To make an object of knowledge (in the strict sense), to make a thing, the prerequisite, Kant urges, is perception in space and time. Without a sensation— and that sensation, as it were, laid out in place and duration— an object of science is impossible. No mere demonstration will conjure it into existence. And with that requirement the old theology and psychology, which professed to expound the object-God and the object- soul, were ruled out-of-order in the list of sciences, and reduced to mere dialectical exercises. The circle of the sciences, therefore, does not lead beyond the 'con- ditioned,* beyond the regions of space and time. It has nothing to say of a 'first cause* or of an ultimate end. Such was the result that might fairly be read from Kant's Criticism of pure Reason,— especially if read without its supplementary sequels, and, above all, if read by those in whom feeling was stronger than 4 2 PROLEGOMENA. [v. thought, or who were by nature more endowed with the craving for faith than with the mind of philosophy. Such a personality appeared in J. H. Jacobi, the younger brother of a poet not undistinguished in his day. Amid the duties of public office and the cares of business, he found time to study Spinoza, the English and Scotch moralists, and above all to follow with interest the development of Kant from the year 1763 onwards. His house at Diisseldorf was the scene of many literary reunions, and Jacobi himself maintained familiar inter course with the leaders of the literary and intellectual world, such as Lessing, Hamann, Goethe. His first considerable works were two novels, in letters, — Allwill, begun in a serial magazine in 1775, and Woldemar, begun in another magazine in 1777; both being issued as complete works in 1781. Both turn on a moral antithesis, and both leave the antithesis as they found it. Here pleads the advocate of the heart: 'it is the heart which alone and directly tells man what is good ' : ' virtue is a fundamental instinct of human nature ' : the true basis of morals is an immediate certainty; and the supreme standard is an 'ethical genius 'which as it were discovered virtue and which still is a paramount authority in those exceptional situations in life when the ' grammar of virtue ' fails to supply adequate rules, and where, therefore, the immediate voice of conscience must in a ' licence of sublime poesy l ' dare, as Burke says, to 'suspend its own rules in favour of its own principles.' There, on the other hand, is the champion of reason, who declares all this sentimentalism ' a veri table mysticism of antinomianism and a quietism of immorality-': 'To humanity,' he says, 'and to every man (every complete man) principles, and some system 1 Jacobi's Werke, v. 79, in, 115, 41?- 2 Ibid., i. 178. v-] JACOB I AND LESSING. 43 of principles, are indispensable/ Woldemar concludes with the pair of mottoes : ' Whosoever trusts to his own heart is a fool/ and 'Trust love: it takes everything, but it gives everything/ In 1780 Jacobi had his historic conversation with Lessing at Wolfenbuttel l. The talk turned on Spinoza. For many years the philosophy of Spinoza had seemed to vanish from the world. His name was only heard in a reference of obloquy, as if it were dangerous to be even suspected of infection with the taint of Atheism. But both Lessing and Jacobi had found him out. The former saw in him an ally in that struggle for higher light and wider views which he undertook in a spirit and with a scope hardly surmised by those he usually wrought with. Jacobi, on the contrary, saw in him personified the conjunction of all those irreligious ten dencies which all philosophy in some degree exhibited : the tendency to veil or set aside God and personality. 'I believe/ says Jacobi, as he began the conversation ' in an intelligent personal cause of the world/ ' Then I am going/ replied Lessing, 'to hear something quite new': and he dryly put aside the other's rhapsody on the 'personal extra-mundane deity 'with the remark 'Words, my dear Jacobi, words/ Jacobi's work Letters on the doctrine of Spinoza (it appeared in 1785) was the beginning of a controversy in which Mendelssohn and Herder took part, and in which Goethe took an interest under Herder's tutorship. To the exact philo logical study of Spinoza it did not contribute much : for the Spinoza whom Herder and Goethe saw as their spiritual forefather was transfigured in their thought to a figure to which Leibniz had almost an equal right to give his name. He upheld to them the symbol of the immanence of the divine in nature : he was the 1 Jacobi's Werke, iv. i. Abth. p. 55 seqq. 44 PROLEGOMENA. [v. leader in the battle against ' philistine ' deism and utili tarianism. With the Kantian criticism of the pseudo-science of theology Jacobi had in one way no fault to find. That reasoning by its demonstration cannot find out God, was to him an axiomatic belief. But the 'man of feeling* felt uneasy at the trenchant methods of the Konigsberg man of logic. He seemed to see the world of men and things passing under Kant's manipulation into a mere collection of phenomena and ideas of the mind. Still more was he sensible to the loss of his God. That sur rogate of an argument for theism which Kant seemed to offer in the implications of the Moral Law did not give what Jacobi wanted. Mere morality is a cold and mechanical principle — he thinks — compared with that infinite life and love which we deem we have in God. The son of man, he felt, was, in virtue of an indwelling genius of conscience, supreme over the moral law : how much more, then, the Absolute and Eternal on a higher grade of being than its mechanical regularities ! If the way of reasoning will not carry us to the Absolute, still less (and that is whither Jacobi wishes to reach) to God, there must be another way : for some thing in him, which may be called Faith or Feeling, Spiritual Sense or Reason, proclaims itself certain of the reality both of God and Nature. There is an objective reality — outside and beyond him— yet some how to be reached by a daring leap, — whereby, out of sheer force of will, he, shutting his eyes to the temporal and the mechanical, finds himself carried over the dividing gulf into the land of eternal life and love. ' I appeal ' he says in his latest utterances 1 'to an imperative, an invincible feeling as the first and un- derived ground of all philosophy and all religion, — to 1 Jacobi's Werkey iv. i, p. xxi. v.] JACOB I ON FAITH. 45 a feeling which lets man become aware of and alive to the fact that he has a sense for the supersensuous/ 'As it is religion which makes man man/ he continues, ' and which alone lifts him above the animals, so it also makes him a philosopher/ Such an organ for the supersensuous is what in his later writings he calls Vernunft (Reason) and distinguishes from Ver stand (Understanding). 'This reason/ says Coleridge (to whom we owe this use of the terms in English) in the Friend, 'is an organ bearing the same relation to spiritual objects as the eye bears to material pheno mena.' It is 'that intuition of things which arises when we possess ourselves as one with the whole/ and is opposed to that 'science of the mere understanding' in which 'transferring reality to the negations of reality (to the ever-varying framework of the uniform life) we think of ourselves as separated beings, and place nature in antithesis to the mind, as object to subject, thing to thought, death to life.' But this Reason is even more than this. It is the direct contact with reality, which it affirms and even is. It apprehends the me and the thee, it apprehends above all the great Thee, God : appre hends, and we may even say appropriates1. And it apprehends them at one bound — in one salto mortale — because if is really in implicit possession of them. Call the step a miracle, if you will : you must admit, he adds, that ' some time or other every philosophy must have recourse to a miracle2/ And yet the asseveration rings false — it shows a womanish wilfulness and weakness in its reiteration. He has the reality; yet he has it not. 'Were a God known/ he says in one place, ' He would not be God/ He yearns with passionate longing to find the living 1 Jacobi's Brief wechsel, i. 330. 3 Jacobi's Werke, iii. 53. 4 6 PROLEGOMENA. [v. and true : he feels himself and the Eternal clasped in one : his faith effects the reality of things hoped for. But, he adds, 'We never see the Absolute ' : the primal light of reason is but faint. It is but a presage— a pre supposition—of the Everlasting. This reason, in short, needs discipline and development, it needs the ethical life to raise it: 'without morality no religiosity/ he says. ' Light,' he complains, ' is in my heart/ but at the moment I want to bring it into the understanding, the light goes out.' And yet he knows— and Coleridge repeats — 'the consciousness of reason and of its revela tions is only possible in an understanding.' There seem to be one or two motives acting upon Jacobi. The 'plain man/ especially if he be of high character and of ' noble ' religiosity, has a feeling that the lust of philosophising disturbs the security of life, and endangers things which are deservedly dear to him. In such an one the 'enthusiasm of logic'— the calm pursuit of truth at all costs, so characteristic of Lessing — is inferior to the 'enthusiasm of life/- a passion in which the terrestrial and the celestial are inextricably blended, where one clings to God as the stronghold of self, and sets personality — our human personality — in the throne of the Eternal. He will be all that is noble and good, if only he be not asked utterly to surrender self. So, too, Jacobi's God— or Absolute (for he leaves his 'non-philosophy' so far as to use both names), is rather the final aim of a grand, overpowering yearning, than a calm, self-centred, self- expanding life which carries man along with it. It would be, he feels, so very terrible, if at the last there were no God to meet us— to find the throne of the universe vacant. Avaunt philosophy, therefore ! Let us cling to the faith of our nature and our childhood, and refuse her treacherous consolations ! V.] JACOB I ON FAITH. 47 With the central proposition of Jacobi, Hegel, for one, is not inclined to quarrel. He too, as he asks and answers the question as to the issues of this and of the better life, might say ' Question, answer presuppose Two points : that the thing itself which questions, answers, — is, it knows ; As it also knows the thing perceived outside itself — a force Actual ere its own beginning, operative through its course, Unaffected by its end, — that this thing likewise needs must be ; Call this — God, then, call that — Soul, and both the only facts for me. Prove them facts? that they o'erpass my power of proving proves them such : Fact it is, I know, I know not something which is fact as much.' But when Jacobi goes on to say that it is the supreme and final duty of the true sage ' to unveil reality/— meaning thereby that, given the feeling, he has only to 'Define it well For fear divine Philosophy Should push beyond her mark and be Procuress to the Lords of Hell,' Hegel withdraws. It is the duty of philosophy to labour to make the perception — the fleeting, uncertain, trembling perception — of faith, a clear, sure, inwardly consistent knowledge: to show, and not merely to assert, that ' the path of (this world's) duty is the way to (that world's) glory/ There is, Hegel himself has said more than once, something opposed to ordinary ways of thinking in the procedure of the philosopher. To the outsider, it seems like standing on your head. It involves something like what, in religious language, is termed conversion— a new birth— becoming a new man. But though such a change always seems to culminate in a moment of sudden transformation, — as if the continuity of old and new were disrupted, the process has a history and a preparation. Of that 48 PROLEGOMENA. [v. pilgrim's progress of the world-distracted soul to its discovery of its true being in God, philosophy is the record : a record which Hegel has written both in the Phenomenologv of Mind, and, more methodically, in his Encyclopaedia. The passage from nature to God — or from man's limitations to the divine fullness — must be made, he urged, in the open day and not in the secret vision when sleep falls upon men. When the aged Jacobi read these requirements of Hegel, he wrote to a friend : ' He may be right, and I should like once again to experiment with him all that the power of thinking can do alone, were not the old man's head too weak for it1.' ' For a philosophy like this,' says Hegel 2, ' individual man and humanity are the ultimate standpoint : — as a fixed invincible finitude of reason, not as a reflection of the eternal beauty, or as a spiritual focus of the universe, but as an ultimate sense-nature, which how ever with the power of faith can daub itself over here and there with an alien supersensible. Let us suppose an artist restricted to portrait-painting ; he might so far idealise as to introduce in the eye of a common place countenance a yearning look, and on its lips a melancholy smile, but he would be utterly debarred from depicting the Gods, sublime over yearning and melan choly — as if the delineation of eternal pictures were only possible at the cost of humanity. So too Philoso phy — on this view — must not portray the Idea of man, but the abstraction of a humanity empirical and mingled with short-comings, and must bear a body impaled on the stake of the absolute antithesis ; and when it clearly feels its limitation to the sensible, it must at the same time bedeck itself with the surface colour of a super- 1 Jacobi's Briefwechsel, ii. 468. 2 Hegel's Werke, i. 15. v.] PSEUDO-IDEALISM. 49 sensible, and point the finger of faith to a something Higher. ' But the truth cannot be defrauded by such a con secration if finitude be still left subsisting; the true consecration must annihilate it. The artist, who fails to give actuality the true truth by letting fall upon it the ethereal illumination and taking it completely in that light, and who can only depict actuality in its bare ordinary reality and truth (a reality however which is neither true nor real) may apply the pathetic remedy to actuality, the remedy of tenderness and senti mentality, everywhere putting tears on the cheeks of the commonplace, and an O God ! in their mouth. No doubt his figures in this way direct their look over the actual heavenwards, but like bats they belong neither to the race of birds nor beasts, neither to earth nor heaven. Their beauty is not free from ugliness, nor their morals without weakness and meanness : the intelligence they haply may show is not without banality : the success which enters into it is not without vulgarity, and the misfortune not without cowardice and terror; and both success and misfortune have something con temptible. So too philosophy, if it takes the finite and subjectivity as absolute truth in the logical form habitual to her, cannot purify them by bringing them into rela tion with an infinite : for that infinite is not itself the true, because it is unable to consume finitude. But where a philosophy consumes the temporal as such and burns up reality, its action is pronounced a cruel dissection, which does not leave man complete, and a forcible abstraction which has no truth, above all no truth for life. And such an abstraction is treated as a painful amputation of an essential piece from the completeness of the whole : that essential piece, and absolute substantiality being believed to consist in the 50 PROLEGOMENA. [v. temporal and empirical, and in privation. It is as if a person, who sees only the feet of a work of art, were to complain, should the whole work be unveiled to his eyes, that he was deprived of the privation, that the incomplete was decompleted.' Jacobi has been spoken of as the leader of this ' Un-philosophy ' of faith. As such his allies lie on one side among philosophers who hold by the deliverances of ' common sense/ by the consciousness of the unso phisticated man shrinking from the waywardness of an idealism that deprives him of his solidest realities. The type of such a philosopher has been drawn by Hegel ' in Krug. But, on the other side, Jacobi touched hands — though not in a sympathetic spirit— with a some what motley band which also had set its face to go to the everlasting gates, but had turned aside to aimless wandering on the Hill Difficulty, or sought too soon the repose of the Delectable Mountains, without due sojourn in the valley of Humiliation or descent under the Shadow of Death. Like Wordsworth, they felt that the world is too much with us : that our true self is frittered away into fragments and passing stages, in which we are not ourselves, — whereby we also lose the true perception of the essential life of nature. Gradually we have sunk into the deadening arms of habit, reduced ourselves to professional and conventional types, and lost the freer and larger mobility of spiritual being. We have grown into versldndige Leute — people of practical sense and worldly wisdom. To such, philoso phy would come — if it could come — as the great breath of life — of 'reason' (Vernunft) which transcends the separations inevitable in practical will and knowledge. But to this band — which has been styled the Romantic School of Germany — the liberation came in ways more 1 Hegel's Vermischte Schriften, i. 50. v.J THE ROMANTIC IRONY. 51 analogous to that craved for by Jacobi. Their way was the way of Romance and Imagination. The principle of Romance is the protest against confining man and nature to the dull round of uniformities which custom and experience have imprisoned them in. Boundless life, infinite spontaneity is surging within us and the world, ready to break down the dams con vention and inertia have established. That inner power is an ever- fresh, ever-restless Irony, which sets up and overthrows, which refuses to be bound or stereotyped, which is never weary, never exhausted, — free in the absolute sense. It is the mystic force of Nature, which they seemed to see ever on the spring to work its magic transformations, and burst the bulwarks of empirical law. It is the princely jus aggratiandi, the sportive sove reignty of the true artist, who is able at any moment to enter into direct communion with the heart of things. The beginning of the nineteenth century in Germany, as well as in England, was a period of effervescence : —there was a good deal of fire, and naturally there was also a good deal of smoke. Genius was exultant in its aspirations after Freedom, Truth, and Wisdom. The Romantic School, which had grown up under the stimulus of Fichte's resolve to enact thought, and had for a time been closely allied with Schelling, counted amongst its literary chiefs the names of the Schlegels, of Tieck, Novalis, and perhaps Richter. The world, as that generation dreamed, was to be made young again,— first by drinking, where Wordsworth led, from the fresh springs of nature, — afterwards when, as often has happened, doubts arose as to where Nature was really to be found, by an elixir distilled from the withered flowers of medieval Catholicism and chivalry, ' Since the Mid- Age was the Heroic Time ' and even from the old roots of primeval wisdom. The £ 2 52 PROLEGOMENA. [v. good old times of faith and harmonious beauty were to be brought back again by the joint labours of ideas and poetry. — ' So, all that the old Dukes had been, without knowing it, This Duke would fain know he was without being it.' To that period of incipient and darkling energy Hegel stands in very much the same position as Luther did to the pre- Reformation mystics, to Meister Eckhart, and the unknown author of the 1 German Theology/ It was from this side, from the school of Genius and Romance in philosophy, that Hegel was proximately driven, not into sheer re-action, but into system, development, and science. To elevate philosophy from a love of wisdom into the possession of real wisdom, into a system and a science, is the aim which he distinctly set before himself from the beginning. In almost every work, and every course of lectures, whatever be their subject, he cannot let slip the chance of an attack upon the mode of philosophising which substituted the strength of belief or conviction for the intervention of reasoning and argument. There may have been a strong sympathy in him with the end which these German contemporaries and, in some ways, analogues to Coleridge, Shelley, Wordsworth, and Byron had in view. No one who reads his criticism of Kant can miss perceiving his bent towards the Infinite. But he utterly rejects the vision of feeling, whether as longing faith or devout enjoyment, as an adequate exposition of the means to this end. Whereas these fantastic seers and sentimentalists either disparage science as a limitation to the spirit, in the calm trust of their life in God, or yearn throughout life for a peace which they never quite reach, Hegel is bent upon showing men that the Infinite is not unknowable, as Kant would have it, and yet that man can not, as v.J THE AGE OF GENIUS. 53 Jacob! would have it, naturally and without an effort enjoy the things of God \ He will prove that the way of Truth is open, and prove it by describing in detail every step of the road. Philosophy for him must be reasoned truth. She does not visit favoured ones in visions of the night, but comes to all who win her by patient study. ' For those/ he says, 'who ask for a royal road to science, no more convenient directions can be given than to trust to their own sound common sense, and, if they wish to keep up with the age and with philosophy, to read the reviews criticising philosophical works, and perhaps even the prefaces and the first paragraphs in these works themselves. The introductory remarks state the general and fundamental principles ; and the reviews, besides their historical information, contain a critical estimate, which, from the very fact that it is such, is beyond and above what it criticises. This is the road of ordinary men : and it may be traversed in a dressing-gown. The other way is the way of intuition. It requires you to don the vestments of the high-priest. Along that road stalks the ennobling sentiment of the Eternal, the True, the Infinite. But it is wrong to call this a road. These grand sentiments find themselves, naturally and without taking a single step, centred in the very sanctuary of truth. So mighty is genius, with its deep original ideas and its high flashes of wit. But a depth like this is not enough to lay bare the sources of true being, and these rockets are not the empyrean. True thoughts and scientific insights are only to be gained by the labour which comprehends and grasps its object. And that thorough grasp alone can produce the universality of science. Contrasted with the vulgar vagueness and scantiness of common sense, that univer- 1 Compare pages 121-142 of the Logic. 54 PROLEGOMENA. [v. salityis a fully-formed and rounded intellect; and, con trasted with the un- vulgar generality of the natural gift of reason when it has been spoilt by the laziness and self-conceit of genius, it is truth put in possession of its native form, and thus rendered the possible property of every self-conscious reason V These words which were taken to heart (unnecessarily, perhaps) by the patron of the Intellectual Intuition rung the knell to the friendship of Hegel with his great con temporary Schelling. Yet this hard saying is also the keynote to the subsequent work of the philosopher. In Hegel we need expect no brilliant aper^us of genius, no intellectual legerdemain, but only the patient unravel ing of the clue of thought through all knots and intricacies : a deliberate tracing and working-out of the contradictions and mysteries in thought, until the contradiction and the mystery disappear. Perseverance is the secret of Hegel. This characteristic of patient work is seen, for ex ample, in the incessant prosecution of hints and glimpses, until they grew into systematic and rounded outline. Instead of vague anticipations and guesses at truth, fragments of insight, his years of philosophic study are occupied with writing and re-writing, in the endeavour to clear up and arrange the masses of his ideas. Essay after essay, and sketch after sketch of a system, succeed each other amongst his papers. His first great work was not published before his 37th year, after six years spent in university work at Jena, following as many spent in preliminary lucubration. The notes which he used to dictate some years afterwards to the boys in the Gymnasium at Niirnberg bear evidence of constant remodelling, and the same is true of his professorial lectures. 1 Phenomenologie des Geistes, p. 54 (Werke, ii). V0 HEGEL'S PERSEVERANCE. 55 Such insistance in tracing every suggestion of truth to its place in the universe of thought is the peculiar character and difficulty of Hegelian argument. Other observers have now and again noticed, accentuated, and, it may be, popularised some one point or some one law in the evolution of reason. Here and there, as we reflect, we are forced to recognise what Hegel termed the dialectical nature in thought, — the tendency, by which a principle, when made to be all that it implied, when, as the phrase is, it is carried to extremes, recoils and leaves us confronted by its antithesis. We cannot, for example, study the history of ancient thought without noting this phenomenon. Thus, the persistence with which Plato and Aristotle taught and enforced the doctrine that the community was the guide and safe guard of the several citizens, very soon issued in the schools of Zeno and Epicurus, teaching the rights of self-seeking and of the independent self-realisation of the individual. But the passing glimpse of an indwelling discord in the terms, by which we argue, is soon for gotten, and is set aside under the head of accidents, instead of being referred to a general law. Most of us take only a single step to avoid what has turned out wrong, and when we have overcome the seeming abso luteness of one idea, we are content and even eager to throw ourselves under the yoke of another, not less one-sided than its predecessor. Sometimes one feels tempted to say that the course of human thought as a whole, as well as that branch of it termed science, exhibits nothing but a succession of illusions, which enclose us in the belief that some idea is all-embracing as the universe,— illusions, from which the mind is time after time liberated, only in a little while to sink under the sway of some partial correction, as if it and it only were the complete truth. 56 PROLEGOMENA. Or, again, the Positive Philosophy exhibits as one of its features an emphatic and popular statement of a fallacy much discussed in Hegel. One of the best deeds of that school has been to protest against a delusive belief in certain words and notions ; particu larly by pointing out the insufficiency of what it calls metaphysical terms, i. e. those abstract entities formed by reflective thought, which are little else than a double of the phenomenon they are intended to explain. To account for the existence of insanity by an assumed basis for it in the ' insane neurosis/ or to attribute the sleep which follows a dose of opium to the soporific virtues of the drug, are some exaggerated examples of the metaphysical intellect which is so rampant in much of our popular, and even of our esoteric science. Positivism by its logical precepts ought at least to have instilled general distrust of abstract talk about essences, laws, forces and causes, whenever they claim an inhe rent and independent value, or profess to be more than a reflex of sensation. But all this is only a desul tory perception, the reflection of an intelligent observer. When we come to Hegel, the Comtian perception of the danger lying in the terms of metaphysics is replaced by the Second Part of Logic, the Theory of Essential Being, where substances, causes, forces, essences, matters, are confronted with what Mr. Bain has called their ' suppressed correlative V 1 Practical Essays, p. 43. CHAPTER VI. THE SCIENCES AND PHILOSOPHY. BY asserting the rights of philosophy against the dogmatism of self-inspired ' unphilosophy/ and by main taining that we must not feel the truth, with our eyes as it were closed, but must open them full upon it, Hegel does not reduce philosophy to the level of one of the finite sciences. The name 'finite/ like the name 'em pirical/ is not a title of which the sciences have any cause to be ashamed. They are called empirical, because it is their glory and their strength to found upon experience. They are called finite, because they have a fixed object, which they must expect and cannot alter ; because they have an end and a beginning, — pre supposing something where they begin, and leaving something for the sciences which come after. Botany rests upon the researches of chemistry : and astronomy hands over the record of cosmical movements to geology. Science is interlinked with science; and each of them is a fragment. Nor can these fragments ever, in the strict sense of the word, make up a whole or total. They have broken off, sometimes by accident, and sometimes for convenience, from one another. The sciences have budded forth here and there upon the tree of popular knowledge and ordinary consciousness, as the interest and needs of the time drew attention 58 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. closer to various points and objects in the world sur rounding us. Prosecute the popular knowledge about any point far enough, substituting completeness and accuracy for vagueness, and especially giving numerical definiteness in weight, size, and figure, until the little drop of fact has grown into an ocean, and the mere germ has ex panded into a structure with complex interconnexion, — and you will have a science. By its point of origin this luminous body of facts is united to the great circle of human knowledge and ignorance. Each special science is a part, which presupposes a total of much lower organisation, but much wider range than itself: each branch of scientific knowledge grows out of the already existent tree of acquaintance with things. But the part very soon assumes an independence of its own, and adopts a hostile or negative attitude towards the general level of unscientific opinion. This process of what we may, from the vulgar point of view, call ab normal development, is repeated irregularly at various points along the surface of ordinary consciousness. At one time it is the celestial movements calling for the science of astronomy: at another the problem of dividing the soil calling for the geometrician. Each of these outgrowths naturally re-acts and modifies the whole range of human knowledge, or what we may call popular science ; and thus, while keeping up its own life, it quickens the parent stock with an infusion of new vigour, and raises the general intelligence to a higher level and into a higher element. The order of the outcome of the sciences in time, therefore, and their connexions with one another, cannot be explained or understood, if we look only to the sciences themselves. We must first of all descend into the depths of natural thought, or of general culture, VI.] THE RISE OF THE SCIENCES. 59 and trace the lines which unite science with science in that general medium. The systematic interdependence of the sciences must be chiefly sought for in the work ings of thought as a whole in its popular phases, and in the action and reaction of that general human thought with the sciences, those definite organisations of know ledge which form sporadically round the nuclei here and there presented in what would superficially be described as the inorganic mass and medium of popular know ledge. Thus, by means of the sciences in their aggre gate action, the material of common consciousness is expanded and developed, at least in certain parts, though the expansion may be neither consistent nor systematic. But so long as this work is incomplete, so long, that is to say, as every point in the line of popular knowledge has not received its due elaboration and equal study, the sciences merely succeed each other in a certain imperfect sequence, or exist in juxtaposition : they do not form a total. The whole of scientific knowledge will only be formed, when science shall be as completely rounded and unified, as in its lower sphere and more inadequate element the ordinary consciousness of the world is now. Up to a certain point the method of science is but the method of ordinary consciousness pursued know ingly and steadily. But ere long the method acquires a distinctive character of its own. It shakes off the pressure of that immediate subservience in which ordinary knowledge stands to man's needs, wishes and interests. Knowledge is pursued — within a wide range —for its own sake, and by a class more or less definitely set apart by humanity for its scientific service, — which is thus performed more systematically and continuously. But the great step which carries ordinary knowledge into its higher region is the discovery, due to reflection 60 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. and comparison, that there is a double grade of reality — a permanent, essential, uniform, substantial being, which is contrasted with an evanescent, apparent, vary ing and accidental. To know a thing is in all cases to relate it to something else : to know it in the higher sense— vere scire — is to relate it to its essence, its sub stantial or universal form, its permanent self. Ordinary knowledge, e. g., fixes a thing by referring to its ante cedents : scientific knowledge refers it to its 'invariable/ 'unconditional' or ' essential ' antecedent, — to something which contains it implicitly, and necessarily, and is not merely by accident or juxtaposition associated with it. To discover this permanent, underlying substance or reality comes to be the problem of science — a problem which may be taken in the widest generality, or re stricted to some one group of existences. What is asked for, e.g., may be the uniformity and essence in the appearance of the diurnal journey of the sun, or it may be the underlying, invisible, nature which displays itself in all the variety of minerals, and in animal and plant life. The one-and-the-same in a diversity of many ; the type-form in individuals : the cause which is the key to understanding an effect that always and un conditionally follows it ; the force which finds different expression in actions — are what Science seeks. In that search two points emerge as regards the method. The first is the importance of quantitative statements or numerical appreciations, and the general law that variations in the qualitative are in some ratio concomitant with variations in the quantitative. Mathe matics, in a word, is found to be an invaluable instru ment for recording with accuracy the minutest as well as the most immense differences of quality. First, it is seen that qualitative differences within a given range, e.g. various colours or various musical notes, can be accu- VI.] MATHEMATICAL SCIENCE. 61 rately expressed by a numerical ratio. But, secondly, it soon appears that even greater divergences of quality, e.g. those of colour and of chemical quality, may pos sibly be reduced to stages on one quantitative scale. It is not unnatural that such experiences should give rise to a hope — and in sanguine minds, an assurance — that all the phenomena of nature are ultimately phases of some common nature — some elementary being — which runs through an infinite gamut of numerically defined adjustments. But the numerical prepossession — as we may call it — creates another assumption. Every number consists of units : every cube can be regarded as an aggregation of smaller cubes, and in measurement is (implicitly at least) so regarded. Transferring this to the physical world, every object is regarded as a composite — a Large, made up by the addition and juxtaposition of many (relatively) Littles. The essentials of the composite are here the elements that compose it : these, by a natural tendency, we proceed to conceive as remaining always unchanged, and giving rise by their peculiar juxtaposition to certain perceptions in the human being. You whirl rapidly a blazing piece of wood, and instead of a discontinuous series of flashes you see one orbit of luminous matter : or, let falling rain-drops take up a particular position in reference to your eyes and the sun, and a rainbow is visible. In both cases there is what may be called an illusion — the illusion, above all, of unity and continuity. Now what is in these cases obviously and demonstrably seen, is, as Leibniz in par ticular has reminded us, the general law of all matter as such. In the extended and material world there is nowhere a real unity discoverable. The small is made up of the smaller ad infinitum 1. But the conclusion 1 Leibniz, ed. Gerhardt, iii. 507 : ' Les atomes sont 1'effet de la 62 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. (which Leibniz drew)— that unity belongs only to Monads and never by any possibility to a material sub stance, was not that commonly reached or accepted. There are — or there must be, — said the prevalent creed, ultimates, indivisibles, indecomposables, simples, atoms. These are the final bricks of reality, out of which the apparent universe is built : each with a maximum, — a ne plus ultra— of resistibility, hardness, fullness, and un- squeezable bulk. Into further details of these ultimate irreducibles we need not enter. It is sufficient to denote the general purport of the conception, and the tendency it implies. In these ultimates supreme reality is understood to lie; and on them at last, and indeed always, rests whatever reality truly exists in any object. All else is secondary — and, comparatively speaking, illusory, — unreal. Any phenomena that may be noted only affect the surface or show of these reals : the inner reality continues one and unchanged. Outside them, around them, is the void — emptiness, non-entity. Yet null and void as it may be, we may, in passing, reply, — this circumambient is the source of all that gives these masses of atoms any dis tinctive reality — any character of true being. Space may be empty enough, — a mere spectre-shell ; and yet it is their differences in spatial circumstance that bring out and actualise what they implicitly are. These ' individual these units of reality, these atoms, are real and knowable only in their relations. So too Time may be contemptuously treated as a passive receptacle : yet it is only by its connexions in the past and the future that the present moment has any actuality it may claim. And time and space are potent agencies — in foiblesse de nostre imagination, qui aime a se reposer et a se hater 9. venir a une fin dans les sous-divisions et analyses : il n'en est pas ainsi dans la nature qui vient de Tinfini et va a 1'infini.' VI.] THE ATOMIC THEORY. 63 popular mode of utterance — whatever the mechanical philosophy may say. But all of these relations are in the realm of unreality. The atoms alone are : and yet the void, which ought not to be, in an unmistakable way is also. To this mysterious vacuum which lies outside (and yet not out side) reality, to this not-being which is, there can only be given a half-negative and baffling name. Let it be called Chance — or let it be called Necessity; let it be called inexplicable Law of co-existence and sequence, — the Force which is the beginning of motion. It is the ultimate key to the mystery — but it is at least a key which no human hand can use; or even lay hold of. It is enough for science if, leaving this ultimate inexplica- bility untouched, it trace in each separate instance the exact equation between the sum of the constituents and the total which they compose, — if it prove that the several items when put together exactly give the sum proposed. Identification — the establishment of quanti tative equations — is the work of science. Identity is its canon, working on the presumption or axiom that there can be nothing in the result which was not in the ante cedents or conditions. Ex nihilo nihil fit. The quantity of energy must always be the same, though its phases may vary, or temporarily avoid detection. Matter, i.e. the ultimate reality, is indestructible. In short, the method of analysis and synthesis, as that of addition and subtraction, is a calculus which takes the form of an equation. So far the inorganic, inanimate world has been mainly in view. If we now turn to the organisms, we find the popular creed expressed in the adage Omne vivum e vivo. No eye has ever seen — though fanatical observers have sometimes so deluded themselves as to think they saw — a living being directly emerge from 64 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. inorganic stuff. The saner student of physiology con tents himself with leaving for the while the crux of the genesis of Life, and examining only the building up of the living creature out of its constituents. Here the atom is called the cell : every organism is a synthesis of cells, and in the cell we have the primary element of organic reality: Omnis cellula e cellula. In the atom we have the ultimate element; in the cell a relative element, — the absolute beginning of a new order of things, — which we may, if we like, choose to treat (though only for logical simplicity's sake) as a gradual development from the other and more primitive, but which, so far as experience and history teach, is equally ultimate in its kind. But be the final constituent (physical) atom, or (physiological) cell, the relation of these constituents is at first conceived by science only as composition, or mechanical synthesis. It is only gradually that science begins to have doubts as to the inviolability and unalterableness of the elements. When the idea— not altogether new — of a 'latent meta-sche- matism ' and latent process within the constituents is entertained and carried out in earnest, science has passed on to a new stage : from mechanical atomism to a dynamic and organic theory of existence. And the governing ideas of scientific logic have then ceased to be co-existence, and sequence, correlation and compo sition : the new category is intus-susception, develop ment, adaptation not only external but internal. Divide et impera is the motto of Science. To isolate one thing or one group of facts from its context, — to penetrate beneath the apparent simplicity, which time and custom have taught ordinary eyes to see in the concrete object, to the multitude of underlying simple elements, — to leave everything extraneous out of sight, — to abolish the teleology which imposes upon Nature VI.] SCIENCE AS DESTRUCTIVE ANALYSIS. 65 a permanent tribute (direct or indirect) towards the supply of human wants, — and to take, as it were, one thing at a time and study it for itself disinterestedly ; that is the problem of the sciences. And to accomplish that end they do not hesitate to break the charmed links which in common vision hold the world together, —to disregard the spiritual harmony which the sense of beauty finds in the scene, — to strip off the relations of means and end, which reflection has thrown from thing to thing, and the sensuous atmosphere of so-called ' secondary ' qualities in which human sense has en veloped each ; and finally to sever its connexion by which 'the whole round world is every way Bound by gold chains about the feet of God.' In those days when reflection had not set in, — when humanity had not yet found itself a stranger in the house of Nature, and had not yet dared to regard her as a mere automatic slave, men had no doubts as to the meaning of things. They lived sympathetically her life. 1 Man, once descried, imprints for ever His presence on all lifeless things : the winds Are henceforth voices, wailing or a shout, A querulous mutter, or a quick gay laugh.' To the extent of his abilities and his culture, indeed man has in all ages read himself into the phenomena external to him. Such readings, in times when he feared and loved his kinsfolk of Nature, were fetichism and anthropomorphism. Gradually, however, forget ting his community, he claimed to be the measure and master of all things : to decree their use and function. But in course of time, when the sciences had eman cipated themselves from the yoke of philosophy, they refused to borrow any such help in reading the riddle of the universe, and resolved to begin, ab ovo, F 66 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. from the atom or cell, and leave the elements to work out their own explanation. Modern science in so doing practises the lessons learned from Spinoza and Hume. The former teaches that all conception of order, i. e. of adaptation and harmony in nature, and indeed all the methods by which nature is popularly explained, are only modes of our emotional imagination, betraying how imperfect has been in most of us the emancipation of human intellect from the servitude to the affections l. The latter points out that all connexions between things are solely mental associations, ingrained habits of expectation, the work of time and custom, accredited only by experience2. There must be no pre-suppositions allowed in the studies of science, no help derived prematurely from the later terms in the process to elucidate the earlier. Let man, it is said, be explained by those laws, and by the action of those primary elements which build up every other part of nature : let molecules by mechanical union construct the thinking organism, and then construct society. The elements which we find by analysis must be all that is required to make the synthesis. Thus in modern times science carries out, fully and with the details of actual knowledge in several branches, the principles of the atom and the void, which Democritus suggested. 1 Spinoza, Ethica, i. 36. App. * Quoniam ea nobis prae ceteris grata sunt quote facile imaginari possumus, ideo homines ordinem confusioni praeferunt : quasi ordo aliquid in natura praeter respectum ad nostram imaginationem esset . . . Videmus itaque omnes rationes quibus vulgus solet naturam explicare modos esse tantummodo imaginandi? Cf. Eth. iv. praef. : Epist. xxxii. 2 ' This transition of thought from the Cause to the Effect pro ceeds not from Reason. It derives its origin altogether from Custom and Experience.' Hume, Essay V. (Enquiry concerning Human Understanding.) 'All inferences from Experience therefore are effects of Custom.' (Ibid.) vi.] SCIENCE AS DESTRUCTIVE ANALYSIS. 67 The scientific spirit, however, the spirit of analysis and abstraction (or of ' Mediation' and 'Reflection '), is not confined in its operations to the physical world. The criticism of ordinary beliefs and conventions has been applied — and applied at an earlier period — to what has been called the Spiritual world, to Art, Religion, Morality, and the institutions of human Society. Under these names the agency of ages, acting by their individual minds, has created organic systems, unities which have claimed to be permanent, inviolable, and divine. Such unities or organic structures are the Family, the State, the works of Art, the forms, doctrines, and systems of Religion, existing and recognised in ordinary consciousness. But in these cases, as in Nature, the reflective principle may come forward and ask what right these unities have to exist. This is the question which the 'Encyclopaedic/ the ' Aufklarung,' the ' Rationalist ' and ' Freethinking ' theories, raise and have raised in the last century and the present. What is the Family, it is said, but a fiction or con vention, which is used to give a decent, but somewhat transparent covering to a certain animal appetite, and its probable consequences ? What is the State, and what is Society, but a fiction or compact, by which the weak try to make themselves seem strong, and the unjust seek to shelter themselves from the consequences of their own injustice ? What is Religion, it is said, but a delusion springing from the fears and weakness of the crowd, and the cunning of the few, which men have fostered until it has wrapped humanity in its snaky coils? And Poetry, we are assured, like its sister Arts, will perish and its illusions fade away, when Science, now in the cradle, has become the full-grown Hercules. As for Morality and Law, and the like, the same condemnation has been prepared from of old. F 2 68 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. All of them, it is said, are but the inventions of power and craft, or the phantoms of human imagination, which the strength of positive science and bare facts is destined in no long time to dispel. When they insisted upon a severance of the elements in the vulgarly-accepted unities of the world, Science and Freethinking, like Epicurus in an older day, have believed that they were liberating the world from its various superstitions, from the bonds which instinct and custom had fastened upon things so as to combine them into systems more or less arbitrary. They denied the supremacy and reality of those ideas which insist on the essential unity and self-sameness in things that visibly and tangibly have a separate existence of their own, and branded these ideas comprehensively as mysticism and metaphysics. They sought to disabuse us of spirits, vital forces, divine right of govern ments, final causes, et hoc genus omne. They were exceedingly jealous for the independence of the indi vidual, and for his right to demand satisfaction for the questioning, ground-seeking faculty of his nature. But while they did so they hardly realised how entirely the spectator is the part, the product of what he surveys, and while surveying treats as if it were but a spot or mark on the circumference of the circle that lies — some way off — around him. l Phenomenalism/ as this mode of looking at things has been called, is false to life, and would cut away the ground from philosophy '. To some extent philosophy returns to the position of the wider consciousness, to the general belief in harmony and symmetry. It reverts to the unity or connexion, which the natural presumptions of mankind find in the picture of the world. The nolo philosophari of the intuitivist, in reaction from the supposed excesses 1 J. Grote, Exploratio Philosophicd . vi.] THE NEED OF RECONSTRUCTIVE THEORY. 69 of the sciences, simply reverted to the bare re-statement of the popular creed. If science, e.g., had shown that the perception of an external world pre-supposed for its accomplishment an unsuspected series of intermediate steps, the mere intuitivist simply denied the inter mediation by appealing to Common Sense, or to the natural instincts and primary beliefs of mankind. Con viction and natural instinct were declared to counter balance the abstractions of science. But philosophy which seeks to comprehend existence cannot take the same ground as the intuitional school, or neglect the testimony of science. If the spiritual unity of the world has been denied and lost to sight, mere assertion that we feel and own its pervading power will not do much good. It is necessary to reconcile the contrast between the wholeness of the natural vision, and the fragmen tary, but in its fragments elaborated, result of science. The sciences break up the rough generalisations or vulgar concepts of everyday use, and make their fixed distinctions yield to analysis. They thus render con tinuous things which were looked at as only separate. But they tend again to substitute the results of their analysis as a new and permanent distinction and principle of things. They are like revolutionists who upset and perturb an old order, and set up a new and minuter tyranny in its place. Gradually, the general culture, the average educated intelligence gathers up the fruit of scientific research into the total development of humanity: and uses the work of science to fill up the lacunae, the gaps, which make popular consciousness so irregular and disconnected. A sort of popular philo sophy comes to sum up and estimate what science has accomplished : and therein is as it were the spirit of the world taking into his own hand the acquisitions won by the more audacious and self-willed of his sons, 70 PROLEGOMENA. [vi. and investing them in the common store. They are set aside and preserved there, at first in an abstract and technical form, but destined soon to pass into the possession of all, and form that mass of belief and instinctive or implanted knowledge whence a new generation will draw its mental supplies. Each great scientific discovery is in its turn reduced to a part of the common stock. It leaves the technical field, and spreads into the common life of men, becoming em bodied in their daily beliefs, — a seed of thought, from which, by the agency of intelligent experience, new increments of science will one day spring. Philosophy properly so called is also the unification of science, but in a new sphere, a higher medium not recognised by the sciences themselves. The recon ciliation which the philosopher believes himself to accomplish between ordinary consciousness and science is identified by either side with a phase of its antagonist error. Science will term philosophy a modified form of the old religious superstition. The popular con sciousness of truth, and especially religion, will see in philosophy only a repetition or an aggravation of the evils of science. The attempt at unity will not approve itself to either, until they enter upon the ground which philosophy occupies, and move in that element. And that elevation into the philosophic ether calls for a tension of thought which is the sternest labour im posed upon man : so that the continuous action of philosophising has been often styled superhuman. If anywhere, it is in pure philosophy that proof becomes impossible, unless for those who are willing to think for themselves \ The philosophic lesson cannot be handed on to a mere recipient : the result, when cut off from 1 Cf. vol. ii. p. 4. vi.] PHILOSOPHY THE STUDY OF UNITIES. 71 the process which produced it, vanishes like the palace in the fairy tale. 1 The whole of philosophy is nothing but the study of the specific forms or types of unity V There are many species and grades of this unity. They are not merely to be enumerated and asserted in a vague way, as they here and there force themselves upon the notice of the popular mind. Philosophy sees in that unity neither an ultimate and unanalysable fact, nor a deception, but a growth (which is also a struggle), a revealing or unfold ing, which issues in an organism or system, constructing itself more and more completely by a force of its own. This system formed by these types of the fundamental unity is called the ' Idea/ of which the highest law is development. Philosophy essays to do for this connec tive and unifying nature, i. e. for the thought in things, something like what the sciences have done or would like to do for the facts of sense and matter, — to do for the spiritual binding-element in its integrity, what is being done for the several facts which are more or less combined. It retraces the universe of thought from its germinal form, where it seems, as it were, an indecom posable point, to the fully matured system or organism, and shows not merely that one phase of pure thought passes into another, but how it does so, and yet is not lost, but subsists suspended and deprived of its narrow ness in the maturer phase. 1 Philosophic der Religion, i. p. 97 : ' Die ganze Philosophie ist nichts Anderes als das Studium der Bestimmungen der Einheit.' See especially Encycl, § 573 (Philosophy of Mind, pp. 192 seqq.). CHAPTER VII. ANTICIPATORY SKETCH OF THE SCOPE OF PHILOSOPHY. THE psychology of the Greeks has to all appearance given the mere intellect an undue pre-eminence, if it has not even treated it as man's essential self. Whether the appearance is altogether sound might be a profitable inquiry for those who most criticise it. At any rate, a later psychology has taught us to regard man as at once a cognitive, an emotional, and a volitional being. It has arrived at this conclusion as it looked at the division that parted off the systems of science from the sphere of conduct and social life, and both from the inner life of sentiment, of love, admiration and rever ence. And the inference was justifiable, in the same way as Plato's when, as he surveyed the triple sphere into which the outward world of his contemporary society was divided, he concluded a triplicity of the soul. If it was justifiable, it was also, as in his case, somewhat misleading. In the outward manifestation, where the letters are posted up on a gigantic scale, one tends to forget that they only spell one word. Their difference and distance seem increased, and we fail to note that, though there are three aspects, yet there is only one power or soul, which exhibits itself under one or other of the three tones or modes. In the actual human being, cognition is always of some emotional ELEMENTS OF MIND. 73 interest and always leads up to some practical result. From different points of view one or other is occasion ally declared to be primary and original ; the others derivative and secondary. At any rate we may say that in the ordinary human being who is still in the garden of preparation and has not yet stepped forth on one of the separate routes of life, his knowledge, his emotional and his active life are in a tolerable harmony, and that each in its little development is constantly followed by the other. But with the outward differentiation an inward went hand in hand. In some cases the intellectual or scien tific, in others the emotional, in others the active faculties became predominant. Human nature in order to attain all its completeness had first of all, as it were, to lose its life in order to gain it. The individual had to sacrifice part of his all-sided development in order that he might gain it again, and in a larger measure, through the medium of society. This process is the process of civilisation : the long and, as it often seems, weary road by which man can only realise himself by self-sacrifice : can only reach unity through the way of diversity, and must die to live. It is a process in which it is but too easy to notice only one stage and speak of it as if it were the whole. It is possible some times to identify civilisation with the material increase in the means of producing 'enjoyment, or with the pro gress of scientific teaching as to the laws of those material phenomena on which material civilisation is largely dependent. It is possible sometimes to take as its test the stores of artistic works, and the extension of a lively and delicate love of all that is beautiful and tasteful. One may identify it with a high-toned moral life, and with an orderly social system. Or one may maintain that the real civilisation of a country presupposes 74 PROLEGOMENA. [VH. a lofty conception and reverent attitude to the supreme source of all that is good, and true, and beautiful. The question is important as bearing on the relation of philosophy to the special sciences. Philosophy is sometimes identified with the sum of sciences : some times with their complete unification. Philosophy, says a modern, is knowledge completely unified. It is of course to some extent a question of words in what sense a term is to be defined. And no one will dispute that the scientific element is in point of form the most conspicuous aspect of philosophy. Yet if we look at the historical use of the term, one or two considerations suggest themselves. Philosophy, said an ancient, is the knowledge of things human and divine. Again and again, it has claimed for its task to be a guide and chart of human life — to reveal the form of good and of beauty. But to do this, it must be more than a mere science, or than a mere system of the sciences. Again, it has been urged by modern critics that Kant at last discovered for philosophy her true province — the study of the conditions and principles of human knowledge. But though epistemology is all-important, the science of knowledge is not identical with philosophy : nor did Kant himself think it was. Rather his view is on the whole in accord with what he has called the 'world's (as opposed to the scholar's) conception of philosophy1,' as the science of the bearing of all ascertainable truths on the essential aims of human reason — teleologia humanae rationis, — in accord, too, with the world's con ception of the philosopher as no mere logician, but the legislator of human reason. This, it need hardly be added, is the conception of philosophy which is implicitly the basis of Hegel's use. Let us hear Schelling. 'A philosophy which in its 1 Kant's Kritik d. r. Vernunft : Methodenl. Architektonik d. r. Vern. vii.] PHILOSOPHY MORE THAN SCIENTIFIC. 75 principle is not already religion is no true philosophy1/ Or again, as to the place of Ethics : ' Morality is God like disposition, an uplifting above the influence of the concrete into the realm of the utterly universal. Philo sophy is a like elevation, and for that reason intimately one with morality, not through subordination, but through essential and inner likeness V But, again, it has more than once been felt that philosophy is kindred with Art. It has been said — not as a com pliment—that philosophy is only a form of gratifying the aesthetic instincts. Schopenhauer has suggested — as a novelty — that the true way to philosophy was not by science, but through Art. And Schelling before him had — while asserting the inner identity of the two — even gone so far as to assert 3 that ' Art is the sole, true and eternal organon as well as the ostensible evidence of philosophy/ Philosophy, therefore, is one of a triad in which the human spirit has tried to raise itself above its limitations and to become god-like. And philosophy is the climax ; Art the lowest ; Religion in the mean. But this does not mean that Religion supersedes Art, and that Philo sophy supersedes religion ; or, if we retain the term 'supersede/ we must add that the superseded is not left behind and passed aside : it is rather an integral constituent of what takes its place. Philosophy is true and adequate only as it has given expression to all that religion had or aimed at. So, too, Religion is not the destruction of Art : though here the attitude may often seem to be more obviously negative. A religion which has no place for art is, again, no true religion. And thus again, Philosophy becomes a reconciler of Art and Religion : of the visible ideal and the invisible God. 1 Schilling's Werke, v. 116. 2 Ibid. v. 276. 3 Ibid. iii. 267. 76 PROLEGOMENA. [vii. Art, on the other hand, is a foretaste and a prophecy of religion and philosophy. But Art, Religion, and Philosophy, again, rest upon, grow out of, and are the fulfilment of an ethical society — a state of human life where an ordered common wealth in outward visibility is animated and sustained by the spirit of freedom and self-realisation. And that public objective existence of social humanity in its turn reposes on the will and intelligence of human beings, of souls which in various relations of discipline and interaction with their environment have become free- agents, and have risen to be more than portions of the physical world, sympathetic with its changes, and become awake to themselves and their surround ings. Such is the mental or spiritual life as it rises to full sense of its power, recognises its kindred with the general life, carries out that kindred .in its social organisation, and at length through the strength social union gives floats boldly in the empyrean of spiritual life, in art, religion, and philosophy. But, what about the special relationship of philosophy to the sciences ? Undoubtedly the philosophers of the early years of the century have used lordly language in reference to the sciences. They have asserted — from Fichte downwards— that the philosophical construction of the universe must justify itself to itself— must be con sistent, continuous, and coherent — and that it had not to wait for experience to give it confirmation. Even the cautious Kant ' had gone so far as to assert that the ' understanding gives us nature ' — i. e. as he ex plains, natura formaliter spectata, viz., the order and regularity in the phenomena— that it is the source of the laws of nature and of its formal unity. The so- called proofs of natural laws are only instances and 1 Kant, Kritik d. r. Vern., Deduction of the Categories, Sect. III. vil.] PHILOSOPHY AND THE SCIENCES. 77 exemplifications, which no more prove them, than we prove that 6x4=24, because 6 yards of cloth at 45. must be paid for by 24 shillings. To assert that this in stance is no proof, is not to reject experience— still less to refuse respect to the new discoveries of science. But it is unquestionably to assert that there is something prior to the sciences — prior, i. e. in the sense that Kant speaks of the a priori, something which is fundamental to them, and constitutes them what they are— some thing which is assumed as real if their syntheses (and every scientific truth is a synthesis) are to be possible. The analysis and exhibition in its organic completeness of this Kantian a priori is the theme of the Hegelian Logic. The Philosophy of Nature stands in the Hegelian system between Logic and Mental or Spiritual Philo sophy. Man — intelligent, moral, religious and artistic man — rests upon the basis of natural existence : he is the child of the earth, the offspring of natural organisation. But Nature itself— such is the hypothesis of the system — is only intelligible as the reflex of that a prioriwhich has been exhibited in Logic. The whole scheme by which the natural world is scientifically held together, apprehended by ordinary consciousness and elaborated by mathematical analysis, presupposes the organism of the categories — these fundamental habits of thought or form of conception which are the frame work of the existence we know. Yet Nature never shows this intelligible world — the Idea — in its purity and entirety. In the half-literal, half-figurative phrases of Hegel, Nature shows the Idea beside itself, out of its mind, alienated, non compos mentis. ' It is a mad world, my masters.' ' The impotence of nature — Ohnmachtder Natur l — is a frequent phrase, by which he indicates the 1 Encyclopaedic, § 250. 78 PR OLE GO MEN A . [vil. a-logical, if not illogical, character of the physical world. Here we come across the negation of mind : chance plays its part : contingency is everywhere. If you expect that the physical universe will display unques tioning obedience to the laws of reason and of the higher logic, you will be disappointed. What you see is fragmentary, chaotic, irregular. To the bodily sense —even when that sense has been rendered more pene trating by all the many material and methodical aids of advanced civilisation — the Idea is in the natural world presented only in traces, indications, portions, which it requires a well-prepared mind to descry, still more to unite. Yet at the same time the indications of that unity are everywhere, and the hypothesis of the logical scheme or organisation of the Idea is the only theory which seems fully to correspond with the data. Nature \ J says Hegel, is the Idea as it shows itself in sense-per ception, not as it shows itself in thought. In thought a clear all-comprehending total ; in sense a baffling fragment. The Idea— the unity of life and knowledge — is everywhere in nature, but nowhere clearly, or whole, or otherwise than a glimpse ; not a logical scheme or compact theory. Nature is the sensible in which the intelligible is bound — the reality which is the vehicle of the ideal. But the ideal treasure is held in rough and fragile receptacles which half disclose and half conceal the light within. Nature in short con tains, but disguised, the idea, in fainter and clearer evidences : it is the function of man, by his scientific intelligence and ethical work, building up a social organisation, to provide the ground on which the ulti mate significance and true foundation of the world may be deciphered, guessed, or believed, or imaginatively pre sented. The verification of the guess or deciphering, 1 Encycl. Sect. 244 (Logic, p. 379). vil.] HEGEL AND SCHOPENHAUER. 79 of course, lies in its adequacy to explain and colligate the facts. The true method and true conception is that which needs no subsequent adjustments — no epicycles to make it work — which is no mere hypo thesis useful for subjective arrangement, but issues with uncontrollable force and self-evidence from the facts. What Hegel has called the ' impotence of nature/ Schopenhauer has styled the irrational Will, and it is from that end, so to speak, that Schopenhauer's philosophy begins. Nature — the basis of all things — the fundamental prius — is an irresistible and irregular appetite or craving to be, to do, to live, — but an appetitus or nisus which ascends from grade to grade —from mere mechanical forces acting in movement up to the highest form of animal activity. But as this ' Will * or blind lust of being and instinct of life gets above the inorganic world, and manifests itself in the animal organism, there emerges a new order of exist ence — the intellect, or the ideal world. Seen from the underside, indeed, all that has appeared now in the animal is a brain and a nerve-system — a new species of matter. But there is another side to the Mind which has thus awakened out of the sleep of natural forces. This intellect is unaware and can never be made aware that it is a child of nature : it acknowledges no superior, and no beginning or end in time. Its natal day is infinitely beyond the age when the cosmic process began its race; before stars gathered their masses of luminosity, and the earth received the first germs of life. As the genius of Art, it arrests the toiling struggle of existence to produce new forms and destroy old ones ; it sets free in typical forms of eternal beauty the great ideas that nature vainly seeks to embody, and as moral and religious life its aim is to 8o PROLEGOMENA. [vil. annihilate the craving and the lust for more and ever more being and to enter in passionless and calm union with the One-and-All. Thus it is, if not absurd, at least misleading, to speak of Hegel's system as Panlogism. Strictly speaking, it is only of the Logic that this is the proper name : there, unquestionably, reason is all and in all. Yet to hold that reason is the very life and centre of things is for philosophy the cardinal article — the postulate which must inspire her first and last steps and guide her throughout. But the Logical Idea, if put at the begin ning, is at first only put as a presupposition, which it is the task of human intelligence to work out and organise. If it be the key which is to explain nature and render it intelligible, it is a key which has only been gained in the process — the long process — by which man has risen from his natural origin — never however parting company with it — to survey and com prehend himself and his setting. The faculty of ' pure thinking/ which is the pre-condition of Logical study, is the result of a gradual development in which animal sense has grown, and metamorphosed, and worked itself up to be a free intelligence and a good will capable of discerning and fulfilling the universal and the eternal. Thus in the Logic the system constructs the pure Idea — the ideal timeless organisation of thoughts or Xoy<»i on which all knowledge of reality rests — the diamond net which suffers nothing to escape its meshes : in the Philosophy of Nature it tries to put together in unity and continuity the phases and partial aspects which the physical universe presents in graduated exemplification of the central truth : and in the Philosophy of Mind it traces the steps by which a merely natural being becomes the moral and aesthetic idealist in whom man approaches deity. vil.] THE REASON IN REALITY. 81 It is indeed Hegel's fundamental axiom that ac tuality is reasonable. But the actuality is not thet/ appearance — the temporary phases — the succession of event : it is the appearance rooted in its essence — the succession concentrated (yet not lost) in its unity. There is room for much so-called irrationality within these ranges. For, when human beings pronounce something irrational, they only mean that their practical intelligence would have adopted other methods to arrive at certain conclusions. They judge, in fact, by their limited understandings and not ex ordine universi. Hegel's doctrine is after all only another way of stating the maintenance of the fittest ; and it is liable to the K same misconception by those who employ their personal aims as the standards of judgment. So too there is reason — there is the Idea — in Nature. But it is there only for the artist, the religious man, and the philosopher ; and they see it respectively by the eye of genius, by the power of faith, by the thought of reason. They see it from the standpoint of the abso lute — sub specie quadam adernitatis. It is therefore a recalcitrant matter in which Nature presents the Idea : or, if recalcitrant suggests a positive opposition, let us say rather a realm in which the Idea fails to come out whole and clear, where unity has to be forced upon and read into the facts. Science, says one writer, is an ideal construction : it implies an abstraction from irregularities and inequalities : it smoothes and sub limates the rough and imperfect material into a more rounded and perfect whole. Its object, which it terms a reality, is a non-sensible, imperceptible reality : what one might as well call an ideality, were it not that here again the popular imagination twists the word into a subjective sense to mean the private and personal ideas of the student. 82 PROLEGOMENA. [vil. But the obvious individual reality never quite in its obviousness equals the 'golden mediocrity* of the ideal. Its myriad grapes must be crushed to yield the wine of the spirit. ' It 's a lifelong toil till our lump be leavened ' — till the ore be transformed into the fine gold. But the gold is there, and in the great laboratory of natura naturans is the principle and agent of its own purifica tion. ' Nature is made better by no mean, but nature makes that mean ' — for nature is spirit in disguise. It is on this side that a certain analogy of Hegel's and Schelling's philosophy of nature with the Romantic school comes out. Nature is felt, as it were, to be spirit-haunted, to give glimpses of a solidarity, a design, a providentiality, which runs counter to that general outward indifference in which part seems to have settled beside part, each utterly indifferent to the other. Romance is the unexpected coincidence, the sudden jumping together of what seemed set worlds apart and utterly alien. It was the sense of this Romance which wove its wild legends of nymph and cobold, of faun and river-god, of imp and fairy, wielding the powers of the elements and guiding the life of even the so-called inanimate world. But it is no less the theme of the fairy tale of science. Even in the austere de monstrations of geometry, and the constructions of mechanics, the un-looked-for slips upon us with gipsy tread. Who has not — in his early studies of mathe matics — been fain to marvel at the almost unexpected consilience of property with property in a figure, sud denly placing in almost ' eery ' relief the conjunction of what was apparently poles asunder ? It is not a mere form of words to speak of beautiful properties of a conic section or a curve. Custom perhaps has blunted our VII.] REASON AND ROMANCE. 83 sense for the symmetries of celestial dynamics, but they are none the less admirable, because we are otherwise engrossed. To the first generation of our century the phenomena of chemistry, magnetism and electricity ap pealed—as they have never since done — with a tangible demonstration of that appetitus ad invicem, that instinct of union Bacon speaks of; and this time in a higher form than in mere mechanism. Polarity — the bifurcation of reality into a pair of opposites which yet sought their complement in each other — eternally dividing only eternally to unite, and thus only to exist — became a process pressed into general service. Lastly, what more admirable than that adaptation of the individual to the environment — and of the environment to the individual — of the organs in him to his total, and of his total to his organs. One in all and All in one : one life in perpetual transformation, animals, plants, and earth and air; one organism, developing in absolute coherence. This was the vision which the genius of Schelling and his contemporaries saw — the same vision which, by accumulation of facts and pictorial history, Darwin and his disciples have impressed in some measure even on the dullest. But there is a profound difference between the spirit of a Philosophy of Nature and the aggregate of the physical sciences. Each science takes the particular quarry which accident or providence has assigned to it, and does its best to 'put out' every piece of rock it contains. But it seldom goes, unless by constraint, and in these days of specialisation it does so less and less, to examine the neighbouring excavation, and see if there be any connexion between the strata. Even within its own domain it is ashamed to put forward too much parade of system. Its method is often like that of the showman in the travelling menagerie: 'And G 2 84 PROLEGOMENA. [vil. now, please pass to the next carriage/ It respects the compartmental arrangement into which it finds the world broken up, and often thinks it has deserved well if it has filled the compartment fuller than before, or succeeded in creating a few sub-compartments within the old bounds. Even the so-called mental and moral sciences when they lose their philosophical character tend to imitate these features. Yet in every science there is an outlook and an outlet, for whosoever has the will and the power, to emerge from his narrow domain on the open fields and free prospect into the first fountains and last great ocean of being. Always, and not least in our own day, the physicist, the chemist, the physiologist, the psychologist, the sociologist, and the economist, have made their special field a platform where they might discourse de omnibus rebus, and become for the nonce philosophers and metaphysicians. It would be a silly intolerance and a misconception of the situation to exclaim Ne sutor ultra crepidam. In the*/ organic system of things ' each " moment " even inde pendent of the whole is the whole ; and to see this is to penetrate to the heart of the thing/ We need hardly go to Hegel to be told that to know one thing thoroughly well is to know all things. The finite, which we inertly rest content with, would, if we were in full sympathy with it, open up its heart and show us the infinite. And yet if the specialist when he rises from his shoe-making, with a heart full of the faith that ' there is nothing like leather/ should proclaim his discovery of it in regions where it was hitherto unsurmised, one may smile incredulous and be no cynic. Philosophy then keeps open eye and ear — as far as may be no doubt for the finer shades and delicate details — but essentially for the music of humanity and the music of the spheres — for the general pur- viz.] PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. 85 pose and drift of all sciences— from mathematics to sociology— as they help to make clear the life of nature and further the emancipation of man. It will seem occasionally to over-emphasise the continuity of science and to make light of its distinctions : it will seem occasionally more anxious as to the order than as to the contents of the sciences : it will remind the sciences of the hypothetical and formal character of much of their method and some of their principles : and some times will treat as unimportant, results on which the mere scholar or dogmatist of science lays great weight. From his habit of dealing with the limitations and mutual implication of principles and conceptions, the philosopher will often be able — and perhaps only too willing— to point out cases where the mere specialist has allowed himself to attribute reality to his abstrac tion. He will tell the analyst of the astronomical motions that he must not take the distinction of cen trifugal and centripetal force, into which mechanics disintegrate the planetary orbit, as if it really meant that the planet was pulled inward by one force and sent on spinning forward by another'. And the scientist, proud of his mathematics, will resent and laugh at the philosopher who lets fall a word about the planets moving in grand independence like 'blessed gods/ The philosopher will hint to the chemist that his formulae of composition and decomposition of bodies are, as he uses them, somewhat mythological, picturing water as atom of oxygen locked up with atom of hydrogen ; and the chemist will go away muttering something about a fool who does not believe in the Encyclop. §§ 266, 269; cf. the lecture-note as given in Werke vii i. p. 97. A large number of paradoxical analogies from Hegel's Nalurphilosophie has been collected by Riehl in his Philosophischer Criticismiis, ii. 2, 120. 86 PROLEGOMENA. [vn. well-ascertained chemical truth that water is composed of these two gases. If the philosopher further hints that it is not the highest ideal of a chemical science to be content with enumerating fifty or sixty elements, and detecting their several properties and affinities 1 ; that it would be well to find some principle of gradation, some unity or law which brought meaning into meaningless juxtaposition, the mere dogmatist, whose chemistry is his living and who shrinks from disendowment, will scent a propensity towards the heresy which sinks all elements in one. And yet, even among chemists, the instinct for law and unity begins to demand satisfaction. A still richer store of amazing paradox and perplexing analogies awaits anyone who will turn over the volume in Hegel's Werke (vii. i) and select the plums which lie thick in the lecture-notes. He will find a great deal —and probably more, the less he really knows of any of the subjects under discussion — that he cannot make head or tail of: language where he cannot guess whether it should be taken literally or figuratively. For Hegel seriously insists on the essential unity and identity of all the compartments of the physical uni verse; he will not keep time and space on one level, matter and motion on another, and senses, suns, plants, passions, all in their proper province. Going far be yond the theory which supposes that all the complex difference of organisation has grown up in endless, endless ages from a primitive indistinctness, so that the gap of time acts as a wall to keep early and late apart, Hegel insists upon their essential unity to-day. And that sounds hard — the herald of anarchy, of the collapse of the ordered polity of the scientific state. It is no doubt probable that Hegel, like other men, made mis takes ; that he over-estimated the supposed discoveries 1 See notes and illustrations in vol. ii. 419. vrr.] PHILOSOPHY OF NATURE. 87 of the day: that he indulged in false analogies, and that he was attracted by a daring paradox. All this has nothing to do with his main thesis : which is, that the natural realm is as it stands an a-logical realm where reason has gone beside itself, and yet containing an instrument — man, and that is mind — by which its ration ality may be realised and restored. In that point at least he and Schopenhauer are at one. CHAPTER VIII. THE SCEPTICAL DOUBT : HUME. WE have seen that an innate tendency leads the human mind to connect and set in relation, — to connect, it may be erroneously, or without proper scrutiny, or under the influence of passions or prejudices, — but at any rate to connect. Criticism occasionally has im patiently banned this tendency as a mere fountain of errors. The human mind, says Francis Bacon, always assumes a greater uniformity in things than it finds ; it expects symmetry, is bold in neglecting exceptional cases, and would fain go beyond all limits in its ever lasting cry, Why and To what end. It varies in indi viduals between a passion for discovering similarities and an intent acuteness to every shade of unlikeness. But notwithstanding these warnings of the hen, the ugly duckling Reason will go beyond what is given : it knows no insuperable limitation. It may be guilty of what Bacon calls ' anticipation ' — an induction on evi dence insufficient — or it may subdue itself to the duty of 'interpretation' of nature by proper methods: in either case, it is an act of association, synthesis, unifi cation. For Not* is dpxri, and knows that it is : it will not yield to clamour or mere rebuke : it, too, cannot be commanded, unless by first obeying it : and Bacon, having duly objurgated the 'mind left to itself/ is obliged to let it go to gather the grapes before they are quite THE INITIAL DOUBT. 89 ripe, and to indulge it with a 'prerogative' of instances. As Mr. Herbert Spencer and many others are never weary of telling us : ' We think in relations. This is truly the form of all thought : and if there are any other forms they must be derived from this V Man used to be defined as a thinking or rational animal : which means that man is a connecting and relation-giving animal ; and from this, Aristotle's definition, making him out to be a ' political ' animal, is only a corollary, most applicable in the region of Ethics. Here is the ultimate point, -from which the natural consciousness, and the energies of science, art, and religion equally start upon their special missions. In ordinary life we attach but little importance to this machinery of cognition. We incline to let the fact of synthesis drop out of sight, as if it required no further study or notice, and we regard the things con nected as exclusively worth attending to. The interest centres on the object— on the matter: the formal ele ment—the connective tissue — is only an instrument of no importance, except in view of the end it helps us to. We use general and half-explained terms, such as develop ment, evolution, continuity, as bridges from one thing to another, without giving any regard to the means of locomotion on their own account. Some one thing is the product of something else : we let the term ' product ' slip out of the proposition as unimportant : and then read the statement so as to explain the one thing by turning it into the other. Things, according to this 1 First Principles, p. 162. It may be as well to remark that Relation is scarcely an adequate description of the nature of thought as a whole. We shall see when we come to the theory of logic, that the term is applicable — and then somewhat imperfectly — only to the second phase of thought, the categories of reflection, which are the favourite categories of science and popular metaphysics. go PROLEGOMENA. [vm. opinion, are all-important : the rest is mere words. These relations between things are not open to further investigation or definition : they are each sui generis, or peculiar : and even if the logician in his analysis of inference finds it advisable to deal with them, he will be content, if he can classify them in some approximate way, as a basis for his subdivision of propositions. This is certainly one way of getting rid of Metaphysics —for the time. But there are epochs in life, and epochs in universal history, when the mind withdraws from its immersion in active life, and reflects upon its own behaviour as on the proceedings of some strange creature, of which it is a mere spectator. At such seasons when we stop to reflect upon the partial scene, and close our eyes to the totality, doubts begin to arise, whether our procedure is justified when we unify and combine the isolated phenomena. Have we any right to throw our own subjectivity, the laws of our imagination and thought, into the natural world ? Would it not be more proper to refrain altogether from the use of such conceptions? Philosophy, said one of the ancients l, begins in wonder, and ends in wonder. It begins from the sur prise that something could be what it purports to be : it ends in the marvel of our having thought anything else possible. Such a phrase well becomes the naive age in which the soul goes freely forth, wandering from one novelty to another, curious to find out all that can be known, — like the young wanderer on the sea-shore whom fresh pebbles and new shells tempt endlessly to fill his basket. But as the ages roll on, and the accu mulations of the past grow heavier in the receptacle, the need of a re-examination of the stores becomes impera tive. The bright colours have faded — and generally 1 Arist. Metaph. i. 2. 26. VIIL] THE INITIAL DOUBT. 91 they fade soon : there has been much picked up in the inexperience of youthful enthusiasm which maturer reflection hardly can think worth carrying further. The duty of doubt and of re-examination of what tradition has bequeathed has been enforced by philo sophy in all ages. For it is the cardinal principle of philosophy to be free — to possess its soul — never to be a mere machine or mere channel of tradition. But, in some ages, this assertion of its freedom has had for the soul a pre-eminently negative aspect. It has meant only freedom from — and not also freedom in and through — its environing, or rather constituting, sub stance. Such an epoch was seen in the ancient world when the New Academy, with its sceptical abstention from all objective assertions, had to protest against the dogmatism of the Stoic and Epicurean schoolmen. In modern times the initial shudder before plunging in has been a recurrent crisis. Each thinker — as he personally resolved to thread his way through the wilderness of current opinion to the realm of certified truth — has had to remind himself (and his contemporaries) that in knowledge at least no posses sions are secured property unless they have been earned by the sweat of their owner's brow. This is the common theme of Bacon's aphorisms in the beginning of the Novum Organum, of Descartes' Discourse of Method, and of Spinoza's unfinished essay on the Emendation of the Intellect. There is indeed a dis crepancy in these utterances as to the measure in which they severally think it needful to insist as preliminary on a kind of moral and religious consecration of life to the service of truth. But a more compelling division arises. The maxim may be understood to say, 'Divest thy mind of its ill-gotten gains, its evil habits, prejudices, and system, and in childlike simplicity prepare thine eye 92 PROLEGOMENA. [viil. and ear to receive in pure vessels the stores of truth which are ready to stream in from the world/ Or it may rather be held to say, ' Remember that thou art a conscious, waking mind; and that every idea thou hast is thine by thine own assent : insist upon thy right of free intelligence, and give no place to any belief which thou hast not raised into full light of conscious ness, and found to be completely consistent with the whole power and content of thy clearest thought/ And, we may add, if the maxim be obeyed too exclusively in either way, it will be obeyed amiss. With Locke the question comes into even greater pro minence. On what conditions can I have knowledge ? How can I be certified that my ideas — the subjective images in my mind — have a reference to something objective and real ? Locke's answer is; not unnaturally perhaps, somewhat prolix, and wanting in fundamental precision of principles. After dismissing the view that, even before experience, there are certain common ideas spontaneously and by original endowment present in all human beings, he goes on to show how we can sufficiently account for the ideas wre actually find by supposing in us an almost unlimited power of joining and disjoining, of comparing, relating, and unifying the various elementary ' ideas ' which make their way into the empty chambers of our mind by the senses. As to the source, the channel, and the nature of these sense-ideas, Locke is obscure and apparently inconsistent : though clearly it should be all important to know how an idea can be caused by, or spring from, a material thing. When in his fourth book he comes to the question of what is the reality, or the meaning of our ideas, he does not really get beyond a few -rather dubiously reasoned-out — conclusions that, although strictly we cannot go beyond ' the present testimony of vni. J LOCKE. 93 our senses employed about the particular objects that do affect them/ we may for practical purposes allow a good deal to the presumptions of general probability. But Locke had also begun to criticise our ideas, in his account of their formation out of the ' simple ideas ' — (which neither Locke nor any other atomist of mind has succeeded in making clear)— which the several senses give, and by observing or reflecting on what goes on or is present in our minds, we ' form,' he says, various ideas. In a style of discussion which is on the borderland between vulgar and philosophical analysis — (never quite false, but nearly always inadequate, because it almost invariably assumes what it ostensibly proposes to explain,) Locke tells us how we get one idea by 'enlarging/ another by 'repeating,' as we please, the bounteous data of the touch and sight. But amongst the compounds there are some of more disputable origin. There are some— e.g. ideas of punishable acts or legal ised states — which are 'voluntary collections of ideas put together in the mind independent from any original patterns in nature.' These, though entirely subjective, are entirely real, because they only serve as patterns by which we may judge or designate things so and so. It is worse with the idea of power, which we only 'collect' or 'infer,' and that not from matter, where it is in visible, but only in a clear light when we consider God and spirits. Still worse, perhaps, is it with the idea of substance, which is a 'collection' of simple ideas with the t supposition ' of an ' incomprehensible ' something in which the collection ' subsists.' Hume put all this rather more pointedly. We have ' impressions,' i. e. lively perceptions by sense. We have also 'ideas,' i.e. fainter images of these, but otherwise identical. An idea should be a copy of an impression. If you cannot point out any such impression, you may 94 PROLEGOMENA. [vm. be certain you are mistaken when you imagine you have any such idea. There is prevalent in the mental world a kind of association ; a ' gentle force ' connects ideas in our imagination according to certain relations they possess. This ' mind* or this ' imagination ' is only a bundle or collection of impressions and ideas ; but a collection which is continually and rapidly changing in its constituents, and in the scale of liveliness possessed by each constituent. When an idea is particularly fresh and forcible, it is a belief, or it is believed in : when faint, not so. Or, otherwise put, the object of an idea is said to exist, when the idea itself is vividly felt*. Really there is no such thing as ' external existence ' taken literally. ' Our universe is the universe of the imagina tion"' : all existence is for a consciousness. Impressions arise in certain orders of sequence or co-existence. When two impressions frequently recur and always in the same order, the custom binds them so closely together, that, should one of them only be given as impression, we cannot help having an idea of the other, which, growing more vivid by the contagion of the contiguous impression, creates, or is, a belief in its reality. Between the perceptions as such, there is no connexion ; they are distinct and independent existences. They only get a connexion through our feeling ; we feel a ' determination ' of our thought to pass from one to another. The one impression has no power to produce the other; the one thing does not cause the other. ' We never have any impression that contains any power or efficacy2/ Hence the power and necessity we attribute to the so-called causal agent and to the connexion are an illegitimate transference from our feeling, and a mistranslation of our in- 1 Treatise of Human Nature (Understanding), iii. 7 and ii. 6. 2 Ibid. iii. 14. viii.] HUME. 95 capacity to resist the force of habitual association into a real bond between the two impressions themselves. The necessity is in the mind — as a habit-caused com pulsion — not in the objects. As with the relation of cause and effect, so it is with others. The identity of continued existence is only another name — an objective transcript — of the feeling of smooth uninterrupted succession of impressions in which our thought glides along from one in easy tran sition to another. And here the coherence and con tinuity of perceptions need not be absolute. A vivid impression of unbroken connexion in a part will, if predominant, by association fill up the gaps and weak points, and behind the admitted breaks in the line of our ideas will suppose— invent — or create an imper ceptible but real continuity in the supposed things. And by this fiction of a continuous existence of our percep tions, we easily lapse into the doctrine that our per ceptions have an independent existence as objects or things in themselves : — a doctrine which according to Hume is contrary to the plainest experience. But if the world is always the world of imagination — of Vorstellung — of mental representation, Hume is aware that we must admit two orders or grades of such representation. We must distinguish, he remarks \ 'in the imagination betwixt the principles which are permanent, irresistible and universal (such as the customary transition from causes to effects and from effects to causes), and the principles which are change able, weak and irregular. The former are the founda tion of all our thoughts and actions.' There are, in other words, normal and general laws of association- such as the relation of cause and effect — which per suade us of real existence. By its own laws, therefore, 1 Treatise of Human Nature (Understanding), iv. 4. 96 PROLEGOMENA. [vm. within the realm of Vorstellung or Mental idea, there grows up a permanent, objective world for all, con trasted with the temporary, accidental perception of the individual and of the moment ; and this serves as the standard or the one common measure by which occa sional perturbations are to be measured. Within the limits of the subjective in general there arises a sub jective of higher order, which is truly objective. This same change of front— as it may be called — Hume makes in morals. There the mind can modify and control its passions according as it can feel the objects of them near or far ; and though each of us has his 'peculiar position/ we can — so creating the ethical basis — 'fix on some steady and general points of view, and always in our thoughts place ourselves in them, whatever may be our present situation * ' : we can 1 choose some common point of view/ and from the vantage-ground of a permanent principle, however dis tant, we have a chance of gaining the victory over our passion, however near. Thus far Hume had gone in the development of idealism. Whether his theory is consistent from end to end, need not be here discussed. But it is evident that Hume was not lost in the quagmire of subjective idealism. The objective and the subjective are with him akin : the objective is the subjective, which is uni versal, permanent, and normal. The causal relation has, in the first instance, only a subjective necessity ; but through that subjective necessity or its irresistible belief, it generates an objective world. But it has been and is the fortune of philosophers to be known in the philo sophical world by some conspicuous red rag of their system which first caught the eye of the bull-like leaders of the human herd. It was so notably with Hobbes 1 Treatise of Human Nature (Morals), iii. i. viii.] KANT AND HUME. 97 and Spinoza; and most of the thinkers whose names appear in the pages of Kant suffer from this curtailment. Descartes, Locke, Leibniz, Berkeley, Hume, are there not the real philosophers, discoverable in their works, but the creatures of historic reputation and of popular simplification who do duty for them. Kant's Hume is therefore a somewhat imaginary being: the product, partly of imperfect knowledge of Hume's writings, partly of prepossessions derived from a long previous training in German rationalism. Such a Hume was — or would have been, had he existed — a phi losopher who 'took the objects of experience for things in themselves/ who 'treated the conception of cause as a false and deceptive illusion/ who did not indeed venture to assail the certainty of mathematics, but held — as regards all knowledge about the existence of things — ' empiricism to be the sole source of principles/ found ing his conclusion mainly on an examination of the causal nexus1. This 'note of warning* sounded against the claims of pure reason — as he calls Hume's Enquiry — was what about 1762 broke Kant's dogmatic slumber and forced him to give his researches in speculative philosophy a new direction. His first step was to generalise Hume's problem from an inquiry into the origin of the causal idea into a general study of the synthetic principles in knowledge. His next was to attempt to fix the number of these concepts and syn thetic principles. And his third was to ' deduce ' them : i. e.; to prove the reciprocal implication between ex perience or knowledge and the concepts or categories of intelligence. 1 Kant, Prolegomena to Metaph. Introduction and Crit. of Practical Reason (on the Claim of Pure Reason, Werke, viii. 167). CHAPTER IX. THE ATTEMPT AT A CRITICAL SOLUTION : KANT. THE Criticism of Pure Reason has been described by its author as a generalisation of Hume's problem. Hume, he thought, had treated his question on the ' relations of ideas ' in their bearing upon ' matters of fact ' mainly with reference to the isolated case of cause and effect. Kant extended the inquiry so as to com prise all those connective and unifying ideas which form the subject-matter of metaphysics. In his own technical language — which has lost its meaning for the present day — he asked, 'Are Synthetic judgments a priori possible ? ' — a question which in another place he has translated into the form, ' Is the metaphysical faith of men sound, and is a metaphysical science possible ? ' By a metaphysics he meant in the first instance the belief in a more than empirical reality, and secondly the science which should give real knowledge of God; Freedom and Immortality, — a science whose objects would be God, the World, and the Soul. From a comparatively early date (1762-4) Kant had been inclined to suspect and distrust the claims of metaphysics to replace faith, and to give knowledge of spiritual reality ; and he had tried to vindicate for the moral and religious life an independence of the conclu sions and methods of the metaphysical theology and KANT'S THEORY OF EXPERIENCE. 99 psychology of the day. But it was not till some years later— in 1770 — that he formulated any very definite views as to the essential conditions of scientific know ledge : and it was not till 1781 that his theory on the subject was put together in a provisionally complete shape. What then are the criteria of a science ? When is our thought knowledge, and of objective reality? In the first place, there must be a given something— a sense-datum — an 'impression' as Hume might have said. If there be no impression, therefore, there can be no scientific idea, no real knowledge. There must be the primary touch — the feeling— the affection — the /£ ne sais quoi of contact with reality. Secondly, what is given can only be received if taken up by the recipient, and in such measure as he is able to appropriate it. The given is received in a certain mode. In the present case, the sensation is apprehended and perceived under the forms of space and time. Perception, in other words, whatever may be its special quality or its sen suous material, is always an act of dating andJocalisa- tipn. The distinction between the mere lump of feeling or sensibility and the perception is that the latter implies a field of extended and mutually excluding parts of space, and a series of points of time, both field and series being continuous, and, so far as inexhausti bility goes, infinite. Thirdly, even in the reception of the given there is a piece of action and spontaneity. If the more passive recipiency be called Sense, this active element in the adaptation may be termed Intellect. Intellect is a power or process of choice, selection, comparison, distinguishing and dividing, analysis and synthesis, affirmation and negation, numeration, of judg ment and doubt, of connexion and disjunction, differen tiation and integration. Its general aspect is by Kant H 2 ioo PROLEGOMENA. [ix. sometimes described as Judgment — the act of thought which correlates by distinguishing ; sometimes as Apper ception, and the unity of apperception. It is, i. e., an active unity and a synthetic energy ; it unifies, and always unifies. It links perception to perception, corre lating one with another— interpreting one by another ; estimating the knowledge-value of one by the rest. It thus 'ap-perceives.' It is a faculty of association and consociation of ideas. But the association is inward and 'ideal' union: the one idea interpenetrates and fuses with the other, even while it remains distinct. Kant's work may be described — in its first stage — as an analysis and a criticism of experience. The term Experience is an ambiguous one. It sometimes means what has been called the ' raw material ' of experience : the crude, indigested mass of poured-in matter-of-know- ledge. If there be such a shapeless lump anywhere,— which has to be considered presently — it, at any rate, is not on Kant's view properly entitled to the name of Experience. The Given must be felt and apprehended : and — to put the point paradoxically — to be felt it must be more than feJt, — it must foe perrei'vprL It must, in other words, be projected— set in space and time : let out of the mere dull inner subjectivity of feeling into the clear and distinct outer subjectivity of perception. But, again, to be perceived, it must be apperceived : to be set in time and space, it must first of all be in the hands of the unifying consciousness, which is the lord of time and space. For in so far as space and time mean a place and an order — in so far as they mean more than an empty inconceivable receptacle for bulks of sensation, in the same degree do they presuppose an intellectual, synthetic genius, which is in all its perceptions one and the same, — the fundamental, original unity of conscious ness. And this analysis of experience is 'transcen- IX.] KANT'S THEORY OF EXPERIENCE. 101 dental.' Beginning with the assumed datum —the object of or in experience — it shows that this object which is supposed to be there -to exist by itself and wait for perception— is created by and in the very act which apprehends it. Climbing up and rising above its habitual absorption in the thing, consciousness (that of the philosophic observer and analyst) sees the thing in the act of making, and watches its growth. We have seen that Kant made free use of the metaphor of giving and receiving. But it is hardly possible to use such metaphors and retain independence of judgment. The associations customarily attached to the figurative language carry one away easily, and often for a long way, on the familiar paths of imagination. The analogy is used even where — if all were looked into— its terms become meaningless. No reader of Locke can have failed, e. g., to notice how he is misled by his own images of the dark room and the empty cabinet : — images, useful and perhaps even necessary, but requiring constant restraint in him who would ply them wisely and to his reader's good. From what has been said above it will be clear that the acquisition of experience, the growth of knowledge, is a unique species of gift and acceptance. The consciousness which Kant describes may be the consciousness of John Doe or Richard Roe : but as Kant describes it, the limitations of their personality, i. e. of their in dividual body and soul, have been neglected. It is consciousness_in_general which_as Kant's theme, just as it is granite in general — and not the block in yonder field,— which is the theme of the geologist. Once get that clear, and you will also see clearly that conscious ness is at once giver and recipient — neither or both : at once receptivity and spontaneity. But — you may reply — does not the material object act (chemically, optically, 102 PROLEGOMENA. [ix. mechanically, &c.) on the sense-organ on the periphery of my body, does not the nerve-string convey the im pression to the brain ; and is not perception the effect of that process, in which the material object is the initial caused In this exposition — which is not unknown in vulgar philosophy — there is a monstrous, almost inextricable, complication of fact with inference, of truth with error. So long as there is an uncertainty — and metaphysicians themselves, we may be reminded, are not agreed upon the matter — as to what we are to understand by cause, effect, and act, what an impression is, and how brain and intelligence mutually stand to each other, it is hardly possible to pronounce judgment upon this mode of statement. Yet perhaps we may go so far as to say that while the terms quoted bear an intelligible meaning when applied within the physiological process they are vain when used of relations of mind to body. There is a sense in which we may speak of the action of mind on body, and of body on mind : but what we mean would perhaps be more unmistakably expressed by saying that the higher intellectual and volitional energies are never in our experience entirely independent of the influences of the lower sensitive and emotional nature. In the metaphysical sense which the terms are here made to bear, they mislead. Action and re-action can only take place in the separateness of space, where one is here and another there : (though, be it added, they cannot take place even on these terms, unless the here and the there be somehow unified in a medium which embraces both). Mens, said Spinoza, is the idea carports1 : he would hardly have said Corpus habet ideam. What he meant would scarcely have been well described by calling it a parallelism or mutual indepen- 1 Spinoza, Eth. ii. 7-13. IX.] IDEALISM AND REALISM. 103 dence, yet with harmony or identity, of body and mind. Apart from body, no doubt, mind is for him a nullity : for body is what gives it reality. But, on the other hand, Mind is the enveloping and including ' Attribute ' of the two : idealism This was the fundamental proposition which Kant contended for ; what he spoke of as his own Copernican discovery : though, in reality, for the student of the history of philosophy it was only the re-statement, in some respects the clearer statement, of the idealism which even Hume, not to mention Spinoza and Leibniz, had maintained. The world of experience— the em-j pineal, objective, and real world— is a world of ideas,' of representations which have place only in mind, of appearances. Space and time are subjective : the foxms of though^ are snhjprtivf> : and vet they constitute phenomenal or empirical or real objectivity. Such language is— it would seem inevitably — misunderstood : and in his second edition, Kant — besides many other minor modifications of statement, — had to defend him self by inserting a 'confutation of idealism/ i.e. of the theory which holds that the existence of objects outside us in space is doubtful, if not even impossible. But no end of argument will ever confute the view that Kant's doctrine is such idealism : until people can be got to rise to a new view of whatsis subjectivity— what is an idea — and what is existence outside us. By 'subjective' the world is in the way of under standing what is due to personal prepossession, void of general acceptability, a product of individual feeling, peculiar and inexplicable tastes. By subjective Kant means what belongs to the subject or knowing mind as such and in its generality : what is constitutive of intelligence in general, what sense and intellect are semper et ubique. Into the question how the human 104 PROLEGOMENA. [ix. being came to have such an intellectual endowment — the question which Nativist psychology is supposed to settle in one way, and Evolutionism in another — Kant does not enter; he merely says where there is know ledge, there is a knower, — a knowing subject so con stituted. It comes after all to the tautology that the reality we know-is a known reality : that knowledge is a growth in the knower, and not an accidental product due to things otherwise unknown. The predicate (or category) ' is ' is contained, implicit, in the predicate ' is known/ or what 'is' puts implicitly, 'is known' puts explicitly and truly. By ' appearance ' the world understands a sham, or at least somewhat short of reality. By appearance Kant understands a reality which has appeared : or, as that is going too far, a something which is real so far as it goes (a prima facie fact), but only a candidate for admission into the circle of reals. And such reality depends on nothing more than its thorough-going coherence with other appearances, its explaining the rest, and being in turn explained by them, — its absolute adap tation to its environment. And this environment all lies in the common field of consciousness, and in the one correlating and unifying apperceptivity of the ego, - that Ego which is the inseparable comrade, vehicle, and judge, of all our perceptions. It is the appearance — but as yet not the appearance of something, — but rather an appearance to >orfor_ something. By an ' idea ' the world in general understands what it is sometimes ready to call a mere idea. And by a mere idea is meant something which is «0t_r£ality, but a peculiarity of an individual mind, or group of minds — a fancy, without objective truth : — something, we may even add, which for many people is located in their own head or brain, cut off by blank bone-walls IX.] IDEALISM AND REALISM. 105 from the open air of real being. By idea (repre sentation, Vorstellung) Kant meant that an object is always and essentially the object of a mind : always relative to a subject consciousness, and implying it, just as a subject consciousness always implies an object. And by ' existence outside us ' the world probably means— for it is imprudent to define and refine too much in this hazy medium of words where we all drowse — existence of things on an independent footing beyond the limits of our personal, i. e. bodily and sentient, self. As regards our own trunk and limbs, most of us, except in some most strange insanity, are not likely ever to be in doubt, and are indeed more likely, after Schopen hauer's model, to take the knowledge of these personalia as the one thing immediately and intuitively certain. We talk freely enough, it is true, about existence outside our own minds ; but it is only a drastic method of stating the difference between a fancy and a fact. And probably we labour under a half-unconscious hallucina tion that our minds are localised in some material 'seat/ somewhere in our bodily limits, and more especially in the central nerve-organs. But, as has been said elsewhere \ the point of view under which Mind is regarded by Kant is that of Con sciousness, and especially perceptive consciousness. He describes, as we have put it above, the steps or conditions under which the single sense-observation is elevated into the rank of an experience claiming universality and necessity. But the whole machinery of consciousness— the form of sensibility and the cate gory of intellect — is originally set in motion by an 1 Encyclopaedia, §§ 415, 420. Consciousness is only as it were the surface of the ocean of mind ; and reflects only the lights and shadows in the sky above it. 106 PROLEGOMENA. [ix. impetus from without : or at least the manipulating machinery requires a raw material on which to operate. Consciousness, or the observer who takes this point of view, feels that it is being played upon by an unknown performer- or that it is attempting to apprehend some thing, which, because the act of apprehension is also to some extent (and to what extent, who can say ?) a trans mutation, it must for ever fail to apprehend truly. It is haunted by the phantom of a real, — a thing in its own right, which can only appear in forms of sense and intellect, never in its own essential being. It is only a short step further — and Kant, if one may judge him by several isolated passages, has more than once crossed the interval, — to treat, after the manner of uneducated consciousness and of popular science, the thing in its independent being as the cause which produces the sensation, or as the original which the mental idea reproduces under the distortions or modifications rendered necessary by the sensuous-intellectual medium. For, if under the terms of one analogy the perception is an effect of the thing, under those of another it is an image or copy of external reality. If this be Kantian philosophy — and it can quote chapter and verse in its favour — Kantian philosophy is one version of the great dogma of the relativity of knowledge. That unhappy phrase seems to have many meanings, but none of absolutely catholic acceptation. It may mean that knowledge of things states their relations — the way they behave in reference to this or that, in these or those circumstances ; and that of an utterly unrelated and absolutely isolated thing, our knowledge is and must be nil. Of a thing-in-itself we can know nothing ; for there is nothing to know. It may mean that knowledge is relative to the recipient or the knower, — that it is not a product which can stand IX.] PHENOMENA AND NOUMENA. 107 by itself, but needs a vehicle and an object in close relation. In this way, too, knowledge is relative to age and circumstances : grows from period to period, and may even decay. And thirdly, the relativity of knowledge may be taken to mean that we (and all human beings) can never know the reality ; because we can only know the phenomenon, i. e. the modified, transmuted, reflected thing which has reconstituted an image of itself after passing the interfering medium. For, first of all, we must strip it — this ' image ' so- called (the vulgar call it the 'thing') — of the secondary qualities (sound, colour, taste, resistance) which it has in the consciousness of a being dependent on his sense- organs : and then, we must get rid also of those quanti tative attributes (figure, number, size) which it has in the consciousness of a spatially and temporally per ceptive being ; — and then ; — but the prospect is too horrible to continue further and face the Gorgon's head in the outer darkness, where man denudes appearance in the hope to meet reality. The fact is, there are too many strands in the web which Kant is weaving, for him or perhaps for any man to keep them all well in hand and lose none of the symmetry of the pattern he designs. To be just, we must, in dealing with him as with any other philosopher, try to keep in view the unity of that design instead of insisting too minutely and too definitely upon its occa sional defects. It is easy to work the pun that a 'critical' philosophy must itself expect to be criticised ; it is more important to remember that by a criticism Kant meant an attempt to steer a course between the always enticing extremes of dogmatism and scepticism, — an attempt to be fair, i. e. just to both sides, and yet neither to sink into the systematised placidity of the former, nor to rove in a mere guerilla warfare with the latter. And it J08 PROLEGOMENA. [ix. is the mere privateer who in the popular sense of the word is the mere critic. Of Kant we must remember that he has the defects of his qualities. He prides himself on his distinctions of sense and intellect, of imagination and understand ing, of understanding and reason ; and with justice : but his distinctions are sometimes so decisive that it is hard work both for him and for his reader to recon stitute their unity. He is fond of utilising old classifi cations to embody his new doctrine : and occasionally the result is like what we have been taught to expect from pouring new wine into old bottles. He draws hard and fast lines, and then has to create, as it seems, supplementary links of connexion, which, if they operate, can only do so because they are the very unity he began by ignoring. One gets perfectly lost in the multitude of syntheses, in the labyrinth of categories, schemata, and principles, of paralogisms, antinomies, and ideals of pure reason. One part of this formalism may be set down to the pedantry and pipeclay of the age of the Great Frederick — pedantry, from which, as we console ourselves, our modern souls are freed. But it arises rather from the necessity of pursuing the battle between truth and error through every com plicated passage in that great fortress which ages of scholasticism had — on various plans — gradually con structed. Kant is always a little of the martinet and the schoolmaster ; but it is because he knows that true liberty cannot be secured without forms and must capture the old before it can plant the new. The forms as they stand in his grouping may often appear stiff and lifeless : but a more careful study, more sym pathetically intent, will find that there is latent life and undisplayed connexion in the terms. Unfortunately the classified cut-and-dried specimens are more welcome ix.] KANT'S ALLEGED SHORTCOMINGS. 109 to the collector, and can more easily be put in evidence in the examination-room. Thus the original question, Are synthetic judgments a priori possible ? is answered — somewhat piecemeal— in a way that leads the reader to suppose it is a question of psychology. He hears so much of sense, imagina tion, intellect, in the discussion, that he fancies it is an account of a process carried on by the faculties of an individual mind. And of course nobody need suppose these processes are ever carried on otherwise than by individual thinkers, human beings with proper names. But scientific investigation is concerned only with the essential and universal. For it, really, sense, imagination, &c. are not so many faculties in a thinking agent : they are grades and aspects of consciousness,— ' powers ' in a process of gradual mental complication (involution). Kant is really dealing with a 'normal' thought with its distinguishable constituent aspects. Only — -he fails to make this explicit and clear. The individualism — the un-historical prepossession — of his age is upon his phraseology, if not upon his thought : and one hardly realises that he is really engaged on human thought and knowledge as a substantial subject of itself apart from its individual vehicles,— on that thought, which lives and grows in social institutions and products, — in language, science, literature, and moral usage, — the common stock which one age be- queathes to the next, but which the later-comer can only inherit if he works for and creates it afresh. If it be a psychology, therefore, it is a psychology which does not assume a soul with qualities, but which expounds the steps in the constitution of a normal intelligence. One may note, without insisting on them too much, the defects of his treatment of the forms of thought. It may be said that, in the first place, the table of the no PROLEGOMENA. [ix. categories was incomplete. It had been borrowed, as Kant himself tells us, from the old logical subdivision of judgments, derived more or less directly from Aristotle and the Schoolmen. Now many of the rela tions occurring in ordinary thought could not be reduced to any of the twelve forms, without doing violence to them. But Kant expressly disclaims ex- haustiveness in detail. He could, if he would : but that is for another season. In the second place, the classifi cation did not expressly put forward any principle or reason, and gave ground for no development. That there should be four fundamental categories, each with three divisions, making twelve in all, seems as inex plicable as that there should be four Athenian tribes in early times and twelve Phratriai. The twelve patriarchs of thought stand as if in equal authority, with little or no bearing upon one another. We have here, in short, what seems an artificial and not a natural classification of the types of thought. But Kant himself has given some explanation of the triad, and a sympathetic interpretation has shown how the four main groups are steps in the solution of one problem l. In the third place, the question as taken up seems largely psycho logical, or subjective, concerning the constitution of the human mind as a percipient and cognitive faculty. But this is necessary, perhaps, to the restricted nature of Kant's problem. He is dealing with the elements that form our objective or scientific consciousness of I the physical world. The deeper question of the place and work of mind in life in general, in law and morality and religion, does not at this stage come before him. That problem in fact only gradually emerges with the Criticism of the Moral Faculty and the Aesthetic Judg- 1 It is not the least of the merits of the exposition in Caird's Critical Philosophy of Immanuel Kant, vol. i. to have brought out this. IX.] KANT'S ALLEGED SHORTCOMINGS. Ill ment. Logic— as the doctrine of the Logos which is the principle of all things, even of its own Other — had to wait for its preparation till it could be matured. In Hegel the question assumes a wider scope, and receives a more thorough-going answer. In the first place the question about the Categories is transferred from what we have called the epistemological or psycho logical, to what Hegel terms the logical, sphere. It is transferred from the Reason subjectively considered as a mere receptive and synthetic human conscious ness to the Reason which is in the world and in history, — a Reason, which our Reason, as it were, touches, and so becomes possessed of knowledge. In the second place, the Categories become a vast multitude. The intellectual telescope discovers new stars behind the constellations named in ancient lore. There is no longer, if there ever was, any mystic virtue supposed to inhere in the number twelve : while the triadic arrange ment is made radical and everywhere recurs. The modern chemist of thought vastly amplifies the number of its elementary types and factors, and proves thai many of the old Categories are neither simple nor indecomposable. Thirdly, there is a systematic de velopment or process which links the Categories to gether, and shows how the most simple, abstract, and inadequate, inevitably lead up to the most complex and adequate. Each term or member in the organism of thought has its place conditioned by all the others : each of them is the germ, or the ripe fruit of another. CHAPTER X. THE CRITICAL SOLUTION, CONTINUED: KANT. KANT'S answer to his question was briefly this. In telligence is essentially synthetic, always supplementing the given by something beyond, instituting relationships, unifying the many, and thus building up concrete totalities. In pure mathematics this is obvious: the process of numeration shows it creating number out of units, and geometry shows elementary propositions leading on to complicated theorems. In abstract physics it is hardly less obvious : there, e. g., the principle of reason and consequent or the persistence of substance are rational and legitimate steps beyond the mere datum. The more important question follows. How are these 'pure' syntheses applicable to real fact? To that Kant replies : They apply, because in all that we call real or objective fact there is a subjective element or constituent. What appears to be purely given, and independent of our perceptions, is a product of per ceptual and conceptual conditions, — is constituted by a synthesis in perception, imagination, conception. Our world is a mental growth — not our individual product, but the work of that common mind in which we live and think, and which lives and thinks in us. Anyhow it is not an isolated self-existing un-intelligent world for ever materially outside us — an other world, X.] KANT ON METAPHYSICS. 113 eternally separate from us ; but bone of our bone, flesh of our flesh, the work realised by our great 'elder brother/ — the Idea of human collectivity — the Reason or Spirit in which we are all one soul. It is therefore no unwarranted step on to a foreign property when we apply the categories of thought and forms of sense to determine objective reality : for objective reality has been for ever made, and is now making, objective and reality by the conscious or unconscious syntheses of perception and imagination. There remains the answer to the same question as regards the objects of Metaphysics. These objects are according to Kant inferences, and illegitimate inferences. They are not necessary elements or factors in the con stitution of experience. In order that there should be experience, knowledge, science, there must be an end less hold of space and time in which to stow it clearly and distinctly away : and there must also be ties and relations binding it part to part, links of reference and correlation, a sort of logical elastic band that will stretch to include infinitely copious materials. But each real knowledge attaches to a definite assignable perception, in a single place and time. From this point we can travel — by means of like points — practically without limit in any direction. But though the old margin fades forever and forever as we move, a new margin takes its place : the limitation and finitude remain : and new acquisitions are always balanced in part by the loss of the old. Yet the heart and the imagination are clamorous, and the intellect is ready to serve them. Such an intellect Kant has called Reason, and its products (Platonic) 'Ideas.' The (Platonic) Idea expresses not so much an object of knowledge as a postulate, a problem, an act of faith. The ' Vaulting ambition' Intelligence 'o'erleaps itself and falls on U4 PROLEGOMENA. [x. t'other/ Unsatisfied with a bundle of sensations and ideas, it demands their abiding unity in a substantial Soul. To simplify the endlessness of physical phe nomena, it sums them up in a Universe. To gather all mental and physical diversities and divisions into one life, it creates the ideal of God. Each single experience, and the collected aggregate of these experiences, is felt to fall short of a complete total : and yet this complete total, the ultimate unity, is itself not an experience at all. But, if it be no object of experience, it is still an idea on which reason is in evitably driven : and the attempt to apprehend it, in the absence of experience, gives rise to the theories of Metaphysics. Everything, however, which can be in the strict sense of the word known, must be perceived in space and time, or, in other words, must lie open to experience. Where experience ends, human reason meets a barrier which checks any efficient progress, but refuses to recognise the check as due to a natural limit which it is really impossible to pass. The idea of com pleteness, of a rounded system, or unconditional unity, is still left, after the categories of the understanding have done their best : and is not destroyed although its realisation or explication is declared to be impossible. There is thus left unexplained a totality which encom passes all the single members of experience — a unity compared to which the several categories are only a collection of fragments — an infinite which commands and regulates the finite concepts of the experiential intellect. But in the region of rational thought there is no objective and independent standard by which we can verify the conclusions of Reason. There are no definite objects, lying beyond the borders of experience, towards which it might unerringly turn ; and its sole authentic use, accordingly, is to see that the understanding is X.] KANT ON METAPHYSICS. 115 thorough and exact, when it deals in the co-ordination of experiences. In this want of definite objects, Reason, whenever it acts for itself, can only fall into perpetual contradictions and sophistries. Pure Reason, there-/ fore, the faculty of ideas, the organ of Metaphysics,) does not of itself 'constitute' knowledge, but merely' 'regulates ' the action of the understanding. By this rigour 'of demonstration Kant dealt a deadly blow, as it seemed, to the dogmatic Metaphysics, and the Deism of his time. Hume had shaken the certainty of Metaphysics and thrown doubt upon Theology : but Kant apparently made an end of Metaphysics, and annihilated Deistic theology. The German philosopher, as Hegel has said and Heine has repeated, did thoroughly and with systematic demonstration what Voltaire did with literary graces and not without the witticisms with which the French executioner gives the coup de grace. When a great Idea had been degraded into a vulgar doctrine and travestied in common reality, the French man met its inadequacies with graceful satire, and showed that these half-truths were not eternal verities. The German made a theory and a system of what was only a sally of criticism; and rendered the criticism wrong, by making it too consistent and too logical *. Science — such is Kant's conclusion — is of the definite and detailed, of the conditioned. It goes from point to point, within the enveloping unity of what we call experience, and which rests upon the transcendental and original unity of consciousness. But a knowledge of the whole — of the enveloping unity — is a contradiction in terms. To know is to synthetise : you cannot syn- thetise synthesis. Knowledge is of the relative : but an absolute and unconditional totality has no relations. We may therefore, possibly, feel, believe in, presuppose 1 Hegel's Werke, vol. i. p. 140. I 2 1 1 6 PROLEGOMENA. [x the absolute : but know it in the stricter sense, we cannot. It may be the object of a rational faith. But as for knowledge, we can get on in psychology without the invisible and immortal soul : we can carry out sciences of the physical universe, without troubling our selves about the ' cosmological ' questions of ultimate atoms or ultimate void, of first beginning and final end : and no proofs will ever prove the existence of that ' ideal' of reason — briefly termed God — which tran scends and completes and creates all existence. Not that such Ideas are useless even in science. They represent — if not without risks — the faith and the pre supposition which underlie the spirit of scientific pro gress, and set before it an ideal perfection which it will do well to strive after, though it can never get beyond approximations. What is perhaps more important : this faith of reason science is as little competent to disprove, as it is incompetent to prove it. Science is not all in all : we are more than mere theoretical and cognitive beings. The logic of science is not the sole code of our spiritual or higher intellectual life ; ' We live by admiration, hope, and love.' The sequel and development of the first Criticism are found in Kant's works on ethics, aesthetics, teleology and religion. Only in one supplementary chapter, and in casual indications as need arises, has Kant made any pronouncement on his view of Philosophy as a whole and as a system. That it is and can only be a system, when it really engages on reconstruction in theory, was of course his fundamental insight. But in his stage of Zetesis l, of testing and sifting the sound 1 Kant from 1762 onwards continues to insist on the necessity for philosophy taking up an analytic and critical attitude to current con ceptions : see especially Werke, i. 95 and 292. x.] KANT'S ETHICS. 117 from the professed, he has confined himself to break ing up the mass piecemeal, and leaving each result in its turn to corroborate and correct the other. Sense and intellect may spring from a common stem ; but let us, he says, deal with them in their apparent separate- ness. Reason practical must no doubt be identical at bottom with reason theoretical : all the more convincing will be the undesigned coincidence between the results of an inquiry into the principles of science, and one into the principles of morals. We have seen that science ultimately rests — though it does not discuss it and would indeed be incompetent to do so — on a faith, a hope, a postulate of the ultimate supremacy of intelli gence, — the faith of reason in its own power (not verifi able indeed by an exhaustive list of actual results) — or in the rationality of the world. For science — though a kind of action and a part of conduct — is a sort of inactive action : an enclave in the busy world, a period of preparation for the battle of life. In the field of conduct the ultimate presupposition, which was for the luxury of science called a reasonable faith or faith of reason, makes itself felt in the more forcible form of a categorical imperative. Or, at least, so it seems on first acquaintance. The command of duty, addressed to the sensuously-con ditioned nature, brooks no opposition and condescends to no reasons in explanation or promises by way of attraction. The moral law claims unconditional au thority: towards its sublime aspect reverence and sheer obeisance is due, utter loyalty to duty for duty's sake. Nothing short of this absolute identification with the Ought and a willingly willed self-surrender of the whole self to it can entitle an agent to the full rank of moral goodness. Such is the form — the synthetic link which joins the sensuous wyill indissolubly with the will reason- Ii8 PROLEGOMENA. [x. able of moral law. Now for its explanation. Humanity, though in the world of appearance and experience always subject to sensuous conditions, is also a power of transcending these conditions. Man is more than he can ever show in visibly single act. He has in him the hope, the faith, the vision of absolute perfection and completeness : but has it not as positive attained vision, but as the perpetual unrest of unsatisfied en deavour, as the feeling and the anticipation of an un achieved idea. And that perfection, that completeness he believes himself to be ; he even in some sense is. Lapses and ill-success cannot quench the faith : for so long as there is life, there is hope. As he pictures out this invisible self, it may assume various forms more or less imaginative. At times it may seem a far away, and yet intimately near, being of beings, — the common father of all souls, the eternal self-existent centre of life and love, the omnipresent bond of nature, the omniscient heart of hearts, — on whom he can lean in closest communion ; though he is only too well aware how often he lives as if God were not, and human beings were roaming specks in chaos. At other times, he looks up to it as to an inner and better self, his conscience, the true and permanent being, which controls his choices and avoidances, which approves and disapproves, commands and condemns : his soul of soul, genius, and guardian spirit. In such a mood to be true to his own self — to follow the very voice of his nature — is to realise his law of life. His Ego is the absolute ego — the reason which is all things. And lastly, there are times when he conceives this better self and true essence as the community of the faithful, as the congregation of reasonable beings, of all perfected humanity. In Kantian phraseology, man under one visible form X.] KANT'S ETHICS AND RELIGION. 119 is the union of an intelligence and a sensibility, of a noumenal with a phenomenal being. He is, indeed, says Kant, the former only in idea : it is only a stand point which he assumes. But it is a standpoint he always does assume, if he is to be practical, i. e. if he is to move and modify the world he finds around him. And what standpoint is that ? What is the law that has to govern his action, the law of the spiritual world? Its supreme law is the law of liberty ; and that law is autonomy. Action— always under law— but that law a self-imposed one. So act that thy will may be thy law, and with thy will the law of all others whatsoever; so act that no other human being may by thy act be deprived of full freedom and treated merely as a thing : so act as to respect the dignity of every human being as implicitly a sovereign legislative. In other words, Morality is a stage of struggle and of progress which bears witness to something beyond. The ' I ought ' represents a transition stage towards the ' I will/ or rather it is the translation of it into the language of the phenomenal world. Morality, in a sense-being, always presents itself as a contest between the good and the evil principle : but in the transcendent and noumenal being which such a being essentially is, —in the reasonable or good will, the victory is already won by the good. Good is the law which governs the world, and which is the strength of the individual life. To the sensuous imagination, indeed, which here is apt to usurp the place of reason, things appear under a somewhat different aspect. There the certainty of self-conquest is forced by the difficulties of apparent failure t6 veil itself under the picture of a perpetual ap proximation through endless ages towards the standard 1 Foundation of Metaph. of Eth. (Werke, viii. 82, 89) : ' Dieses Sollen ist eigentlich ein Wollen.' 120 PROLEGOMENA. [x. of perfect goodness : the confidence that the world is reasonable is presented under the conception of a God who makes all things work together for good to the righteous : and the autonomy of reason presents itself as the postulate of freedom to begin afresh, absolutely untrammeled by all that has gone before. Thus the kingdom of reason is represented as having its times and seasons ; as making determinate starts, and work ing up to a consummation in the end of ages. But implicitly Kant's idea of reason's autonomy, — of the ' I ought ' as in its supreme truth an ' I will,' — is an eternal truth. The 'standpoint,' so to call it after Kant, is the standpoint which explains life and conduct and which makes conduct possible. It is the assertion that the completeness is, and is my inmost being, the source of my action, my chief good, and that chief good not a gratification or satisfaction to be looked forward to as reward, but essential life and self-realisation. And this joy is what is hidden under the austere gravity of the categorical imperative. The Criticism of the Judgment-faculty is Kant's next step towards providing a completer philosophy. Ostensibly it owes its origin to the need of supple menting the treatment of Understanding and Reason by a discussion of Judgment, and of considering our emotional as well as our cognitive and volitional appre ciations. What it really does is to minimise still further the gulf left between the intellect and nature — between the natural and the spiritual world. The intellect, said the first criticism, makes nature : it makes possible the general outlines of our conception of the world around us as a causally-connected system, in which a permanent being undergoes perpetual alteration, and manifests phenomena subject to mathematical conditions. In tellect, in short, has staked out the world which is the X.] KANT'S AESTHETICS. 121 object of the practical man, and of his adviser the scientist. But there is another world — the world of beauty and sublimity — the world which art imitates and realises. The interpretation Kant gives to the aesthetic world is as follows. The fact of beauty is a witness to the presence in the mere copiousness of sensible existence of a sub-conscious symmetry or spirit of harmony which realises without compulsion and as if by free grace all the proportion and coherence which intellect requires. Nature itself has something which does the work that intellect was charged with, and does it with a subtle secret hand which does not suggest the artificer. The fact of sublimity, on the other hand, indicates the presence of an even greater spirit. For beauty may seem — from what has been said — to be only an unbought accrement to the com modities of life — facilitating the task of the practical intellect. But the sublime in nature speaks of some thing which is greater than human utilities and prac tical conveniences. It reveals a something which is in sympathy with our essential and higher self, and therefore stirs within us the keen rapture of the traveller who sees from afar his home in 'rocky Ithaca,' but a something which is cold to daily wants and vulgar satisfactions, and therefore strikes upon us a gelid awe. Another world yet remains, which appeals neither to our utilitarian science, nor to our higher sentiments of artistic perfection. This is the world as the home of organic life, and perhaps itself an organism. The organism is apt to be a poser for the ordinary cate gories of mechanical science. Here the part contains the whole, not less than the whole contains the part : the cause is an effect, as well as cause, of its effect. One thing is in another, and the other in it : ' the 122 PROLE GOMENA . [x . present is charged with the past, and pregnant of the future/ — as the great founder of modern teleology often said. In the plant and the animal the natural world has to a certain degree reached an ideal unity which is also real. Reason — the syllogism — is here not merely introduced from without, as when man manipu lates, but is the immanent law of a natural life, — the end working out itself by its own means and act. The fact admitted in these creatures suggests extending the conception of organism (or teleology) to nature as a whole. From this point of view Nature may almost be said to have a history — because it is almost conceived as having one abiding self which in apparent un consciousness wonderfully simulates the purposive adaptation of conscious life. The older vulgar tele ology was somewhat mechanical : it regarded the natural world outside of— or as it said, below — man as having no end of its own, but in its series subserving man's commodities. In the teleology of Kant the supreme end is still in a way man, and still there is a little of the mechanical about it : but it is not to promote man's happiness, understood as that probably must be in a selfish sense, but to produce in him the worthiest agent to carry on to its highest the rational process of development. The struggles and pains of natural existence, the laws of life, the competition of rivals, are all means in the hands of nature to produce an autonomous being. Kant says, a moral agent. But a moral agent has been already explained as an intelli gence certified unto truth and a self-centred will whose law is the law of the cosmos, — whose plan of life, if we so put of it, is essentially a concentration in miniature and in individuality of the system ordained by the all- present God. It is true that Kant, after all these soarings, checks X.] KANT'S TELEOLOGY. 123 enthusiasm by the words 'not that we can know this, or that it is so : but our nature with unmistakable tendency bids us act as if it were so. Logic will hardly justify it— but life seems to demand it.' And some have replied : 'let us trust the larger hope/ CHAPTER XL SYNTHESIS AND RECONSTRUCTION I FICHTE. To get the full effect of a new doctrine it must be brought into contact with a mind unshackled by those traditional prepossessions which clung to its original author. Kant, essentially by training a man of the school, was by heart and character essentially a seeker after the wider ends of the larger world. His lesson is on one hand the scholar's disproof of pretended science, and on another an appeal and an example to the mere scholar to make his philosophy ample for the whole life, and co-extensive with the -whole field of reality. His first disciples who stand forward as teachers caught only the first part of his message, and sought to set theoretical philosophy on a sounder basis. Johann Gottlieb Fichte — perhaps the least professional of great philosophical professors — with a resolute will, a passion for logical thoroughness, and great impulse to force mankind to be free and to realise liberty in an institu tion — was the first who really grappled with the search ing questions that arose out of Kant's message to his age. His was a Kantism, not certainly always of the letter, nor indeed always of the spirit : yet for all that, there was substantial justice in his claim that his system supplied the presupposition which gives meaning and interconnexion to Kant's utterances1. It is, says 1 Cf. notes and illustrations in vol ii. p. 399. KANT AND FICHTE. 125 the proverb, the first step that costs. And Fichte took that step. Before his impetuosity the cautelous clauses which besmirched the great purpose of Criticism shrunk away, the central truth was disengaged from its old- fashioned swaddling clothes, and openly announced itself as a renovating, almost a revolutionary principle. But, as v/as to be expected, the unity and force are paid for by a considerable surrender of catholicity. If Kant's utterances are fused into comparative simplicity, the unification does not embrace the whole of the Kantian gospels. What Fichte did in his earlier stage — the stage by which he counts in the history of philosophy — was to emphasise and exhibit in his systematic statement that priority or supremacy of the ' practical ' over the ' theoretical ' reason which Kant had enunciated, and to put in the very foreground that self or Ego which Kant had indicated, under the title of 'transcendental unity of apperception/ as the focus which gives coherence and objectivity to experience. But to put the final presupposition at the head and front of all, as a principle originating and governing the whole line of procedure, is really to modify in a thorough-going way the whole aspect of a doctrine and its inner constitution. Kant's way is quiet analysis : from the given, or what is supposed given, up re- gressively to its final presuppositions, its latent prius. He shows you the thing is so, apparently without effort, by judicious application of the proper re-agent, as it were. Fichte, on the contrary, pours forth a strong current of deduction : Let it be assumed that so and so is, then must, or then shall, something else be ; and so onwards. Instead of a glance at the secret substructure of the world, you see it, at a magician's mandate, building itself up ; stone calling to stone, and beam to beam, to fill up the gaps and bind the walls together. And you 126 PROLEGOMENA. [xi. must not merely read or listen. You are summoned as a partner in the work ; a work the author feels, only half-consciously, he has not yet quite accomplished, and where therefore he complains of the bystander's dullness. This, one may say, was a new conception, certainly a new practice, of philosophy. Kant had indeed hinted that the pupil in philosophy must 'symphilosophise'; but practically, even his aim had been to describe or narrate a process of thought with such quasi-historical vividness and detail that the listener was sympathetic ally carried through the succession of ideas which were called up before him. What had been generally given in philosophical literature was a sort of historical ac count of how thoughts happened : a succession of pic tures presented with the interposition here and there of a little reasoning, expository of connexions. You en listed your reader's sympathy : you set his imagination to work by translating the logical process into a his torical event — the Logos into a Mythos — and blending with your narrative a little explanation as to general drift and relations, you left him to himself to enjoy the Theoria. The nearest approach Fichte makes to this polite and easy method is in the ' Sun-clear Statement,' where he, as he says, attempts to 'force the reader to understand ' him. But probably these things cannot be forced. And for the rest Fichte's characteristic attitude is to request, or command, his reader (or pupil) to think with him, to put himself in the posture required, to perform the act of thought described. He has not merely to be present at the lecture, but personally to perform the experiment. It is not a mere story to be heard and admired and forgotten. De te, O pupil ! fabula narratur. If it be a play, you are the actor as well as the onlooker : and the play is not a play, but the drama — the nameless drama — of the soul trans- XI-] FICHTE'S ME THOD. 1 2 7 acted in the unseen sub-conscious depths which bear up its visible life. You do not therefore begin by getting a fact put before you. Your fact, in philosophy, must be your own act: not something done and dead, passive, a thing, but something doing, alive, active : your intro spection must be, let us say, an experiment in the growing, responsive, quick life, not anatomy of the mere cadaver. Think, therefore, and catch yourself in the act of thinking. Get something before your mind's eye, and see what it involves. It matters not what you perceive or feel : only realise it fully and penetrate its meaning and implications. It is of course the percep tion of something here and now. And you would be, in ordinary life, eager to get on to something else— to associate the present fact to something perceived else where, to draw conclusions about things yet to come. But if you philosophise, you must check this practical- minded impatience and concede yourself leisure to ponder deeply all that the single perception involves. Be content to sit awhile with Mary, by the side of Rachel of old. Let Martha bustle about. Fichte tells you that your perception rests,— and you, you see that it rests, on the ' I am that I am/— on the I = I, i. e. on the continuity, identity, and unity of the percipient self. Make the statement of what you perceive, believe it, that is, assert it: and you have— done what? You have pledged your whole self—falsus in tmo, falsus in omnibus— to its truth: its background is your whole and one mental life. And is that all ? You have also called the world to witness : your statement— if, as it professes, it form an item however slight in the realm of knowledge— requests and expects every other ' I ' to acknowledge your perception. Your certainty of the fact rests on the certainty of your self: and your self is 128 PROLEGOMENA. [XT. a self certified by its ever-postulated identity with other selves, so on ad infinitum. In affirming this (whatever be your statement) you affirm the Absolute Infinite Ego. Heaven and earth are at stake in every jot and tittle1. At which plain frankness there was much cachin- nation and even muttering among the baser sort. Even wiser heads forgot — if they ever knew — that Leibniz a century before had startled the world of his day by a view that 'the Ego or something like it2 ' was, under the name of monad, the presupposition of each and every detail of existence in any organic total. It was useless for Fichte to repeat3 that his philosophical Ego was not the empirical or individual ego which he in this every-day world had to provide clothes and com pany for. It is hard to persuade the world that it does not know that ' I am I/ and what that means. Later, therefore, Fichte, going along with the movement of contemporary speculation, and willing to avoid one source of confusion, tended to keep off the name of Ego from the absolute basis of all knowledge and experienced reality. But unquestionably the absolu- tising of the Ego is the characteristic note of his first period in philosophy : and it rings with the spirit of the heaven-storming Titan. It means that the cardinal principle and foundation of man's conscious moral and intellectual life is identical with the principle of the Universe, even if the Universe seem not to know it. It means that self-consciousness — the certainty that I am I and one in all my manifestations — is the highest word yet uttered. In, or under, the surface of human knowledge and belief in reality, there is a tran scendental Ego — a self identical with all other selves,— 1 Cf. notes and illustrations in vol. ii. p. 387. 2 Leibniz, Werke, ed. Gerhardt, iv. p. 392. 3 Cf. notes and illustrations in vol. ii. p. 393. xi.] THE ABSOLUTE EGO. 129 infinite, unlimited, unconditional, absolute. The cer tainty of human knowledge — and therefore of all reality in consciousness — is the Absolute, — an absolute cer tainty and knowledge — but an absolute with which I identify myself, — which I am, and which is me. This is the absolute thesis— the nerve and utter basis-laying— at the ground, or rather under the ground, of all I know, feel, and will. This, then, is the thesis at the very foundation of all Wissenschaft : and therefore figures at the head of the Wissenschaftslehre, — the name Fichte gives his fundamental philosophy. But alone it is powerless. A foundation is only a foundation, by being built upon. The position must be defined by counterposition : thesis by antithesis: ego by non-ego. Ego, in fact, is first made such, as set against you. In other words, the per ception we assumed to start with does not merely suppose and indeed pre-suppose the absolute Ego ; but it sets in the absolute Ego an ego and a non-ego, — sets against the lesser ego, something limiting and limited, something defining it in one particular direction ; or, if the original consciousness we started to examine was an act of will, then, it may be said, the non-ego appears as about to be limited and defined by the Ego. Be our consciousness, therefore, practical or theoretical, of action or of knowledge, its fundamental characteristic is the conjunction (correlation with subjugation) of an ego and a non-ego. It is always a synthesis of an original antithesis 1 ; of self and not-self. But every 1 The antithesis has two members : the partial ego, and the non- ego, which confronts. The synthesis is a putting together two separate things, so as to correlate them ; but it falls short of what would be understood in some present usage by 'synthetic unity' which has a certain mystical ring. It is important for a student of Schelling or Hegel to remember this distinction of synthesis from ' absolute unity ': e.g. Schelling, Werke, v. 43. 130 PROLEGOMENA. [xi. such synthesis which brings together into one a self and a not-self, is possible only in the original thesis of a greater self — an absolute Ego — which includes the not-self and the self it contrasts within its larger self. The unity of the first principle 1 (A = A, or 1 = 1) parting or distinguishing itself into the opposition of A versus not- A, Ego set against non-ego, re-asserts itself again in consciousness (perception of objects, and action upon them by will) as synthesis, i. e. a conjunction (not a real union). And this synthesis is either the limitation of the Ego by the non-ego or the limitation of the non-ego by the Ego. The former gives the formula of theo retical, the latter that of practical consciousness. We begin with the absolute Ego. It is absolute activity, utter freedom. It is the source of all action, all life. Yet if thus implicitly everything, it is actually nothing. To be something, it must restrict itself, set up in itself an antithesis : — by the setting up of a not-self, at once limit and realise itself: translate itself from ideal absoluteness and unconditionality into a reality which is also limited and partial. All consciousness and action exhibit this antithesis of a limited self and an outside and adversative other-being; but'the antithesis rests upon the medium of a larger life, a thesis which transcends and includes the antithesis, and which leads to that alternating adaptation of the two sides to one another (their synthesis) which actual experience pre sents as its recurring phase 2. The Wissenschaftslehre 1 A— A is the more purely logical formula: /— - / presents it as a personal and metaphysical identity. The A, which is A, is to be distinguished from the A which is opposed to not-A. But it is Fichte's standpoint to insist on their being one Ego. 2 To give this interpretation of the larger Ego as Life and Blessed ness is to assume that the teaching, e. g. of the Anweisung zum Seligen Leben, is the logical deepening of the earlier language about the Ego. XI. J THE ABSOLUTE EGO. 131 leaving the absolute Ego in the background deals with the play that goes on in human experience between the correlatives to which it has reduced itself; — the antago nism, but the moderated and overruled antagonism, of Ego and non-ego. Observe the contrast to the ordinary methods of expression. Popular language — if the popular philo sophers are to be trusted as its exponents— says 'an impression is produced by an external object on the senses, and causes an idea in the mind/ The 'object* works a series of marvellous effects on a mind, which— to begin with — is hardly describable as anything more than an imagined point of resistance, getting reality by being repeatedly impinged upon \ Fichte's statements are rather interpreters of the vulgar phrases, which say ' I hear, I see ' ;— as if, forsooth, the ' I ' did it all. According to Fichte, the 'I/— the absolute 'I,' is the real (but secret) source of the position in which con sciousness finds itself limited by a non-ego. But within the finite ego and its consciousness there is no remi niscence or awareness of this its great co-partner's — the absolute ego's— act. For the finite consciousness, the beginning of its activity — i. e. of all empirical conscious ness, lies in an impulse or stimulus from without — a mere somewhat of which we can predicate the very minimum of attributes. It is only/. ru 218 PROLEGOMENA. [xvn. asked at all — what induction is, what are its relations with deduction, and what is the place of either in the process of knowledge. And as the process of know ledge is the path to reality, it must also ask about the nature of this goal, — reality and truth. It is all very well for the narrower Logic to formulate in terms the methods actually employed in sciences : to state in abstract canons what is there seen in life and action. But a Science of Logic — an epistemology — (and a genuine epistemology cannot claim to be anything short of an ontology) must face the fact of science itself— must ask how the ideas of the knower must — or otherwise they are not knowledge — embrace and contain the reality of the known. The other and narrower Logic is and will remain a theory of forms of reasoning— a transcript in fainter terms of the procedure of science in any given step it takes upward to generals or down ward to particulars : but the logic which deals with knowledge as such, in its systematic entirety, — the transcendental Logic, in short, must have a real value, an invincible relation to reality. The formal Logic — the logic of Mill and Hamilton — must be carried back to its principles, to its first step : and that first step which will also be the last step, and the inspiring principle of every intermediate step, is that of Intelli gence (Aristotle's Nous), of which the products or manifestations are Xo'yot, i. e. definite conceptions, cate gories, formulations of rules and principles of definite range, — determinations or special types of unity. Mill really faced the problem of method to better effect when he came to deal with a class of questions in which he was really interested, and which moreover have for epistemological purposes the advantage of being as yet unreduced into the rank and file of dis ciplined science. These questions are those dealing xvii.] SOCIOLOGICAL METHOD. 219 with man, his mental and moral nature, and history. Even its advocates or patrons occasionally admit that there is no accepted idea of what Sociology is or does. Its name at least expresses a longing towards a unity, or a presentiment that there is some underlying unity and common method in the group of what are loosely called the moral, or the historical, or the social and political sciences. But sociology is, as most people will allow, the name of a science unrealised — the felt and consciously-apprehended need of a science, and the dissatisfaction with the existing state of knowledge in certain departments. And undoubtedly it was with problems of social science, — problems of politico- economic and socio-ethical or socio-religious matters, that Mill's interests were mainly engaged. Like his master in this department, Auguste Comte, he wanted to carry into the topics which he was chiefly bent upon that ' scientific ' precision which they by pretty general admission lacked, and which revolutionary movements had shown they greatly needed. But he could not help seeing that the 'induction* of dynamics and physics was not exactly the instrument he was in search of. Theory and hypothesis here demanded a much larger share in the process than in the more mathe matical sciences. Causes and effects in reality here rolled round into each other, instead of remaining calmly fixed, one set here, and the other there. Of course even here — i. e. in organic and concrete sciences — it is possible to introduce observation and experi ment, — no doubt, with greater effort and constraint, but still not altogether impracticable. But the artificial and mutilative character of such experimentation is felt here in a way different from its pressure in other cases. And what is more important, to institute an experiment or set on foot a scientific observation (and 220 PROLEGOMENA. [xvn. to observe means to watch a definitely restricted natural process with a view to answer some question about it), presupposes — as we have already seen— a tolerably definite provisional theory as to the general lie of the country to be investigated. Only when the country has been reasonably well mapped out in provinces and provided with some system of roads, can these problems of detail — questions to be answered Yes or No — be profitably put. And it is — in some parts of the historical sciences at least — somewhat premature to put questions requiring a categorical reply. There is only the vague malaise of felt difficulty to guide us. We do not, in many cases, know what it is that we want to know ; for, it demands a good deal of wisdom and trained art to put the proper or reasonable question, — so much so, indeed, that to succeed in formulating your question fully is equivalent or nearly equivalent to being able to answer it. The value of observations and experiments — which are ways of putting nature to the question and it may be to the torture— depends entirely upon the knowledge and the command of general ideas possessed by the observer and experimenter. And the same may be said of the reduced and tabulated conspectuses of the results of many observations and experiments which are called Statistics. Their value depends on the truth and breadth of view which presided at their collection and arrangement '. The historical or genetic method is the method of 1 Statistics only define — and primarily for the imagination — the general laws and principles on which they rest. The clear-cut mathematical form strikes and 'catches on,' where a more universal statement sounds vague and glides off. Hence, as one says, they may prove anything. The fact is, they prove nothing. They only illustrate in diagrammatic form the theory which presided at their collection. To emphasise the fundamental nature of ethics for human development you need only say that conduct is three-fourths or XVII.] THE METHOD OF DEVELOPMENT. 221 Science in general, but considered and employed under a limited aspect. And under its more comprehensive aspect it may be called — though no name is unimpeach able—the method of development. Now the essence of the idea of development — as was clearly shown by Leibniz — is the refusal to admit external interference, and the resolve to let a thing explain itself by itself. It does not, like the mechanical method, manipulate the thing from outside— try to add it up out of factors or items fashioned and fabricated after some external standard. Nor does it, like the chemical, look at the result as an inexplicable alteration, due apparently to a mere stroke of combination or disintegration — yet not obviously reducible to a mere equivalent of its ele ments. On the contrary, it recognises in the object a certain independence or originality, yet also the presence of an immanent law which does not wait for the outsider to put it together, but constructs itself, as it were, after a plan of its own. There is in the so-called object, though we do not at first sight recog nise it, the same originative principle both analytic and synthetic, as we own in thought. The object is — in a true logic — a process, a self-completing process, and not merely an object, mechanical, or other object. It changes, grows or decays, while we observe, unless for brief instants we cut it off from its connexions and arrest its development. And our observation, if truly scientific, must be sympathetic with its process of change. It is neither a mere thing to be explained and construed ab extra : nor a mystery of sudden trans formation to be passively accepted ; but a growth, a history, to be sympathetically watched and under stood, — understood, because it follows the same order (as to some minds the precision rises with the denominator of the fraction) £$ of human life. 222 PROLEGOMENA. [xvil. as the movement of our own thought in the process of knowledge. Similia similibus cognoscuntur^ . One sometimes hears it asked by paradoxical critics at which end a history should begin. And to ordinary dogmatic recklessness, paradoxical the question may well seem. Begin at the beginning, no doubt, is the vulgar reply ; which in this case is understood to mean from the earliest point in date (that, of course, being easily ascertained, and a thing known to all men). But, — so Plato long ago well raised the difficulty which will always confront us, — are we to go from the begin nings, or towards the beginnings ? And it does not quite solve the question to say that we are to begin with what is known : for under that word the same difficulty re-appears. Can you really know one end without the other ? To the vulgar partisan of historical method, its precept means Go to the earlier, if you wish to understand the meaning, the value, and the elements constitutive of the later and subsequent. Begin with origins, with the earliest elements, the phases that first appear ; and thus you will get light to see the later as they really stand. That this is a common interpretation of the historical method is notorious. To explain Homo sapiens, one is told to study the ape, — the nearest analogue of his lost or missing progenitor : to understand the contemporary horse, go to eohippus, or hipparion, or however his early prototype may be 1 The resolute misinterpretation — as it often seems — of the maxim that like is known by like, — is a curious chapter in the history of Logic. All knowledge is based upon, — or, to speak more simply, is — the identity of differents : of differents, which in knowledge are identified, — of identity which in knowledge is put under difference. And yet the ordinary meaningless talk on this matter seems to assimilate knower and known to two separate things (or persons^, who casually and, we may add, inexplicably know each other : which is mythology, perhaps, but not epistemology. XVIL] FACTS AND PROBLEMS. 223 at present named and recognised. And in all this there is a truth — or least a half-truth. But let us equally recognise the other half of the truth. If past throws light on present, present throws not less light on past. You propose, let us say, to write a history of Greece. A wordy philosophy, wise in its own conceit and in fine phrases, will advise you to approach the subject without prepossession or prejudice. So far, good. But what is meant by the absence of prepossession or prejudice ? Not a blank openness to impression, not a mere pas sivity ; but if passivity at all, a wise passivity : if open ness, the openness of the trained judge. The advice, so often associated with Francis Bacon, to get rid of all false pre-conceptions, of all idola, is one which it is easy to mistake in an over-zeal to follow it. That mere negation of prejudices which we call childish innocence is no match for the craft by which Nature seeks to keep or disguise her secrets. The free con sciousness, the unbiassed mind, is not the easy result of one great act of renunciation, but the work of con tinued self-discipline, self-conquest, self-realisation. If you are not to impose upon the thing a pre-conception alien to it, neither must you rashly give yourself away to the thing, or to the first whims which accident puts upon you as the thing. What seems a fact or thing is only a candidate for the post of thing or fact : and its credentials need to be examined, and compared with other evidences. To detect a fact, therefore, is only possible for a tried and tested consciousness which by patience and self-mastery has won the key of interpre tation. What Bacon apparently meant— though, as often happens, in his eagerness to combat a prevailing folly, he sometimes overshot himself in statement — was to insist on the eternal wedlock of the mind and things, of things and the mind, as the sole and sufficient 224 PROLEGOMENA. [xvil. condition for the reality of knowledge and truth. The mind may not presume to do without things, or things to domineer the mind ; — or the result is a windy and frothy vanity. And the wedlock is eternal : in his own eloquent words, ' the mind itself is but an accident to knowledge1/ and he might have added, so also are things : for, as he says, ' the truth of being and the truth of knowing is all one ' : only in the bond of knowledge are things true and real, — being otherwise only ' perma nent possibilities/ or possibilities barely even permanent — or not even possibilities. Yet he scarcely realised that his ' due rejections and exclusions ' and negations were a fundamental constitutive element in those facts of which he habitually emphasises only the positive side. He therefore who would understand — or would write — the history of Greece must really in his studies begin at both ends— both at the Greece of to-day, and at the Greece of Solon, or what earlier period may be taken as the start of Greek history. With perhaps the least qualified dogmatism, one may assert that he will begin with the Greece of to-day ; or if he deals solely with Ancient Greece he will begin with the full blaze of Hellenic civilisation which still has a pale reflection in the modern world, and gradually work back to the beginnings. It is no doubt customary to begin Greek history, say, with the Homeric Age, and work down wards, as it is customary to begin a formal treatise on geography with the general features of the earth's shape and surface. But that beginning represents really the temporarily accredited and accepted result of a process which, starting from the other end, has worked backwards to commencements or origins. 1 Bacon : ' In Praise of Knowledge ' (a mere leaflet of much sig nificance towards estimating his true grandeur). On the Conjugium of Mens and Universus see Novum Orgcinum, distrib. op. xvil.] THE METHOD OF HISTORY. 225 And the teacher, in particular, will do well not to imitate too slavishly the method of the formal treatise. A day may come — or may have come — for example, for Greek history to start from periods long anterior to the supposed or traditional date of the wars around the wall of Troy. But when it does so, it will have done so by more thoroughly ransacking the Greece of to-day : and so disclosing the secrets of what is termed pre-historic Greece. Then, conversely, when modern diggings on Greek soil reveal the features of an earlier than what was erewhile to older historians its earliest past, the reconstruction of that early people's life reflects a new light on the directions and the limitations of its subsequent civilisation. We see better into the reality of Homer, and even of Demosthenes — into their ideal glory and their historical limitations, when we explore the cradle in which their race's life was erst fostered, and the rock out of which they and nature hewed them. And this is no peculiarity of Greece. The deepest research into the social institutions which control the England of to-day is the best propaedeutic for the study of Anglo-Saxon times ; and the same is true vice versa. Nor, again, is the truth of the proposition confined to what we ordinarily mean by history. The Greek poet has said 'Art had to wait on and welcome chance, and chance to wait on Art ' : or as we may paraphrase it, if every invention and discovery is in a measure a lucky chance, it is a luck that only falls to the wisely prepared head and hand. The casual event falls as a germ of new construction or theory only on an intelli gence ready to welcome it, — prepared with its complement in the spirit of an idea, eager to take shape. The means again, in the arts and crafts, is not only a means to something else ; it is also a means to its own end, Q 226 PROLEGOMENA. [xvil. to realise or perfect itself. The rude tool of the savage, for instance, is not merely a means to supply his wants : it is also a means towards completing and improving itself, and towards perfecting itself by constructing an ampler tool, which supersedes it, because it can do all and more than all the work of the earlier, or can do it more economically. All progress that deserves the name is an incessant and continuous revision of a first step : a re-adaptation of an old instrument : a repeated and unending self-correction. It is only a partially- true symbol of human advance to speak of it as a line : unless we add, by another piece of symbolism, that the line is only the protracted or extended phase in which the form of time drags out for us the magnified and organised point-nucleus. It is a truth — which we are only too ready to forget or discount — that the savage (and he bears with justice both epithets, 'the noble savage/ and ' the brute barbarian ') is not something left happily behind us, in the onward march of civilisa tion ; but that he is, however much we may fancy him suppressed and superseded, still present, at least ' ideally ' in the finest products of humanity, and may hap only too likely — as the Russian is said, when scratched, to betray his original Tartar breed — to burst out on provocation into a grim reality. The Pullman car of to-day retains within it for the archaeologically- trained eye the rudiments of the primitive wain of the primitive nomade : and the careful study of either end of the scale will not merely throw a marvellous light on the excellencies or the defects of the other, but will probably also tend in the impartial observer to moderate the self-gratulations of modern advance. For it is only those whose view ranges within narrow limits that are over-impressed by the magnitude of the advance made in the ' last new thing.' xvn.] PROGRESS TRUE AND FALSE. 227 If progress were but the addition of bit to bit, of new bits to what is already there, or if we could change this, and leave that unchanged, — as the word perhaps verbally means, and as many people at any rate seem to understand it, progress might indeed seem an easy thing, and to be undertaken with a light heart. For, it would appear as if we could lose nothing, and might probably (indeed, as enthusiasm and forgetfulness of the merits of the past are in certain periods ready to urge, must certainly) gain. But it is a more serious matter when we realise that we must move altogether, if we really are to move at all ; i. e. really are to make progress, and not merely change, so to speak, from one foot to rest on another. For progress, — if it be what it is expected to be, and what it must be if it does what it is expected to do— is an organic, and not merely a me chanical or chemical change. A mechanical change is only a nominal or formal change : a chemical is more than change ; but in organic change, that which changes also abides, and the new is not merely other than the old, and not merely a re-arrangement of the old, but the old transmuted, — the same yet not the mere same1. Progress in short is always the unity of differentiation and integration. It must not be an externality, nor a mere dead product of a transformation scene, but a continuous growth, inwardly digested, made part and parcel of the collective life, which it has thereby rendered more full, real, and not merely made less intense at the cost of some extension. In true progress, which is only another name for true growth, nothing is quite lost, but only changed, retained in a richer shape and a fuller reality. How far such progress is possible, 1 The said mere same is not really the same at all. Nobody in his senses predicates sameness except where he also sees differences : or, the term always implies relation. Q 2 228 PROLEGOMENA. [xvil. except in limited and finite spheres : how far progress in one involves necessarily deterioration in another and how, therefore, progress is not attributable to the Absolute, are questions we need not here discuss. But so far at least we may go as to say that a progress which does not follow the natural law of development and carry on into the future the worth and substance of the past, is not a progress which any general en thusiasm ought to be spent upon. Development then has two faces, one to the future and another to the past. And what is called the historical method is apt to emphasise only one of the two aspects, just as, it may be added, practical con siderations are often likely to produce an opposite but equally partial bias in favour of the future. The historical method in incapable hands is liable to lead to unprofitable sighs,— not unaccompanied by a certain luxury of tears — over the lowly hole of the pit — it may even be the filth and brutishness, out of which so much of noble humanity (for thither the interest of develop ment always reverts) has been dug ; and in empty heads the practical, the vulgarly-utilitarian satisfaction is liable to equally vain fits of self-applause on our magnificent progress. But both the self-depreciation of him who loiters regretfully round the beggarly rudiments, and the self-laudation of glorious 'improvements' looking derisively on less glorious days, are unworthy of the reasonable and scientific spirit. The philosophical method does not allow itself to be imposed upon by the lapse of time, and insists that in a sense the past contained the present — that, as the poet says, the child is father of the man. Not indeed contained in any grosser or more delicate mechanical way. The coming development does not necessarily lie prefigured — if we had the proper microscope to see it— as a germ in the XVIL] DEVELOPMENT. 229 first and original state. That may be, or may not be. Yet prefigured it is by the law of its structure, or in the intelligible unity by which only can its existence be understood and construed. But if this be the method of real development, in the growth of nature, and the progress of history, it is also the method of that supreme product of historical pro gress, the spirit and system of philosophy. Thought, also, the culminating stage in which the spirit of man becomes conscious of itself and of its universe, will move or grow on the same lines as that of which it is the comprehension and theory. It will begin at the two ends, and each beginning will complete and presuppose the other. Nature will suppose and yet lead up to Spirit or Mind : Spirit or Mind will throw light on the mystery of Nature : Being will point to knowledge or Idea ; and Idea show itself the basis of Being. Or, if we consider the triple division of the philosophic system, as it runs in Hegel's Encyclopaedia, we can see how misleading it may be to take that one order as absolute. To understand it thoroughly we must begin with each of the three in turn : so as thus to realise that each does not except figuratively succeed the other, but that in each an aspect of the whole truth is pre sented which had been put by the other parts somewhat in the background. In each part there is a definition and a revelation of the Absolute. But each is also, as it were, a projection, a perspective view, a condensed or expanded image of the other. In each the Absolute is one and whole, in some more veiled, more restricted, and more meagre than in others ; but the veil, and the restriction, and the emptying, are self-imposed : and for that reason the veil is really transparent, the restriction is negatived, and the emptying is not only a self-humilia ting but a self-ennobling irony — the irony of the Absolute CHAPTER XVIII. THE RANGE OF PERSONALITY. THE difference between the conceptions of reality held by Aristotle and Plato respectively is that where Plato said Being, Essence or Substance (<>vaia\ Aristotle said Activity (eWpytia). To be is to act, to be active. To the outsider — the plain man of philosophic legend, it seems at first that a thing must be before it can do : that you must have an agent before you get an action. And, in a way, Aristotle admits this not quite satisfac tory criticism. Every activity presupposes, he allows, a power to act, a potentiality : every actual presupposes an implicit or a mere possibility. Existence seems, as it were, to be doubled ; or the mere surface-being is turned into a subject which has a predicate. But if the existence is to be real, it has to include both elements, and with the latter or the actuality, as its crown. Nor is this all. The possibility which issues forth in action may be fairly called self-realisation. That is to say: A — the hypothetical agent — acts, does sor" ?thing : and in so doing, seems to go forth and beyond itself, to externalise itself. Or, A is acted upon, and thus seems to be diminished. But what it ex ternalises, or puts forth, is after all what it ts : it puts forth itself: and, on the other hand, if it be a patient, it is no less an agent and self-limitative. What a REALITY AND SELF-REALISA TION. 2 3 1 thing really is, is what it makes itself be : what it allows itself to be made, that it really is. Yet further, if the word self-realisation be taken in its fullness of meaning, —if there be really a self, and it be realised, then this self-realisation, which is the truth or more developed conception of being, seems to imply or postulate in it a self-consciousness, an awareness of the process of com pleted being,— completed in its return from utterance of possibility to self-fruition or in its re-assumption of itself. To us, of course, as beings aware of what we do and achieve, this is simple enough : but it is also true of things, that we only understand them, in so far as we put them in, or invest them with, the same activity and apperception of activity as we are familiar with in our own experience. The veriest materialist cannot help speaking of things as agents, as behaving, as having a function. He would, no doubt, if he were to be cross-examined, refuse to identify himself with the primitive anthropomorphism, or at least zoomorphism of the natural man who sees the river run and the clouds sweep the sky; and he would probably mutter some thing referring to people who cannot see when they ride a metaphor to death. Still less, perhaps, would he be inclined to adopt the spiritualistic or animistic hypo thesis of philosophising physicists, like Fechner, who would accredit even the plants at our feet, and the stars in the sky, with souls, or soul-like centres of their life. But, however he may shrink from what we may call the ontological consequences of his language, there is no doubt that for him the meaning of the world -its reality and truth, is obtained by an interpretation in terms which, rigidly employed, imply their environment by a self-consciousness to which they are relative. Take from him the tacit assumption (which he often finds it difficult to realise just because it is the founda- 232 PROLEGOMENA. [xvin. tion of all his language) that reality is in the last resort a self-conscious reality, and his words become meaning less, or what he might think worse, metaphorical. To Bacon, who, though not without a strong specu lative impulse, approached philosophic dicta from the standpoint of an average intelligent Englishman (and it is on that account that his remarks are often so instructive), it seemed a grave fault of the Stagirite to define the soul, that ' most noble substance/ by words of the second intention. Without substance — a solid something as basis of act and event — the reality of the soul seemed likely to fare badly. Behind conscious ness he, like many others, felt there must be a some thing of which consciousness is the state, act, or pre dicate and attribute. The thinking must come from a thinker. There must be a permanent subject of thought — a persistent substance which does not dis appear when thinking for the nonce stops. And think ing is according to common experience very liable to stops and interruptions. Both Bacon and Locke felt that without this refuge to fall back upon, personal identity was in a bad way, or personality itself little better than a delusion. And therefore when Aristotle, and his modern followers, treated soul and mind as essentially definable by the terms activity, self-realisa tion, it has been freely urged against them that they are tampering with the pearl of great price which all our hopes and aspirations fondly guard. And this is a subject on which there is inevitably a good deal of misunderstanding. And the misunder standing will probably last so long as one set of writers flaunts over it that blessed word Personality as a holy, a sacrosanct thing, like the visionary cross with its inscription In hoc signo vinces : and as another set treats it as a mere fetish, under which is hidden nothing xvili.] PERSONALITY. 233 better than stock or stone, or a heap of old bones. Perhaps some concessions might well be made on both sides. And the first of them would be to try to come to some clearer understanding what the term in question means. And, on that point, if we follow the example of Aristotle and examine popular usage, to see if it can help us to any consistent use of the term, we shall find that by personal as opposed to real we mean something peculiarly attached to the individual, of which he cannot divest himself as of other outward things, though it also is an outward thing1. The person in this narrowest sense means the body ; and if the epithet is further extended it still expresses what is directly manipulated through the members of the living agent, and is more or less closely attached to it. Yet if it means the body, we must be careful to add that it is the body, regarded not as such but as the representative, the outward manifestation, the insepar able sign or symbol of a spirit, an intelligence and a will. The person is the visible or tangible pheno- menon of something inward, — the phase or function by which an individual agent takes his place in the common world of human intercourse and interaction — his peculiar and definite part in the general or universal world and field. Personality thus mingles or unifies in it an universal and an individual aspect or element : it hints that the universal work always has in reality an individually- determinate tone, — that nothing in the world, even if it be called the same, is really and actively the same. Si duo idem faciunt, non est idem quod faciunt. Thus, 1 The legal use of the distinction between ' real ' and ' personal ' is only partly ' logical/ and largely retains traces of the larger logic of life and history. Yet, roughly speaking, personal property is what we can, so to speak, carry on our backs or in our pockets. 234 PROLEGOMENA. [xviil. what separates personality from individuality is simply that in the narrower or abstracter use of the latter term there is an absence of the due subordination of all individuality to universality, and of all universality to individuality. Personality, in short, is an individuality which is not a mere freak, not merely different from other things, but also in itself charged with a universal meaning or function. Yet even this is not enough to describe it. It is the individuality of an intelligence : the flesh and blood, and, in a secondary degree, the outward things, stamped with intelligence. Every member of a kind, every natural existence, has this double character; this convergence or union of universal and individual. In being this individual object, it is at the same time a universal, and vice versa. But in the attribution of personality there is involved something beyond what is common to all creatures. And that something, we may first of all say, is this. Whereas in the case of other things the individuality is distinctly subordinate, and each is reckoned primarily by its kind, in the case of persons we can almost declare that the universality is subordinate to the individuality. This union of individuality and universality in a single manifestation, with the implication that the individuality is the essential and permanent element' to which the universality is almost in the nature of an accident, is what forms the cardinal point in Personality. And one can understand, when the distinction is thus put, the obvious and palpable antagonism in which the view stands to the central principles of Spinoza '. 1 See Spinoza, Cogitata Metaph., Pars II. cap. 8: 'Nee fugit nos vocabulum (Personalitatis scilicet) quod theologi passim usurpant ad rem explicandam : verum quamvis vocabulum ncn ignoremus eius tamen significationem ignoramus : quamvis constanter credamus, in visione Dei beatissima Deum hoc suis revelaturum.' For Hegel, it xvill.] PERSONALITY. 235 We speak of a man as a Personality when we wish to note the fact that he is no mere manufactured article, the representative of a common type, with nothing to choose between him and a thousand others, but that he is, as it were, one of a thousand, one ' Whom nature printed and then broke the type,' that he has in the highest sense ' distinction/ the nobility of nature's own patent. Other things exist, so to speak, for the sake of their kind, and for the sake of other things ; a person, in the strictest sense, is never a mere means to some thing beyond, but always at the same time an end in itself or himself. Other things are mere examples in illustration of a law that rides superior to them and over rules them : the person is a law unto himself. He has the royal and divine right of creating law — of starting by his exception a new law which shall henceforth be a canon and a standard. For in such a personality when he claims his full rights there is the visible immanence of the divine and universal— or there is the visible unity of the eternal and the temporal. He rules as the natural king, the great ruler whose judg ment and authority are better than the complex code of common laws : he guides as the artistic genius who sees truth steadily in a single intuition and in that single picture sees it whole l. But when we ask if such a personality is found in the field of actual experience and history, there arises a may be noted, Person, so far as he uses the term at all, bears its restricted legal and juridical sense. A person is a free intelligence, which realises that independence by appropriating an external thing as its sign and property. It probably belongs therefore to a world in which people count rather by what they have than by what they are ; the world of law where rights and duties tend to oppose each other. This is not the highest kind of world for human beings. 1 This one may call the Platonic ideal of the State, where Equity rules supreme in the incarnate spirit of wisdom, — a guide adapting 236 PROLEGOMENA. [xviil. divergence of opinions. It is at any rate matter of common experience that there is a good deal of unjusti fied identification of the self with the universal — identi fication in which the universal suffers violence and is taken by force. There are only too often cases where the personal interest is allowed to disguise itself under a semblance of zeal for the common good, and that even without conscious intent or act of deception. No good and noble deed, Hegel has said, can ever be done without faith in its goodness, and zeal for its attain ment : without a holy passion and fervour of devotion, which exceeds the cold service of duty rendered for duty's sake \ But it is equally true and equally to be remembered that this interference of personal passion and disinterested interest has defaced the noblest causes and made flow endless torrents of fanaticism and per secution. A personality in which the universal was perfectly incarnated in the individual would be in truth a God amongst men. And it is probably a more likely occurrence that where the individual as such arrogates to himself the privilege of the universal, there should be seen not the deeds of the god, but the ebullitions of the beast that is in man. A personality, then, in popular language, and per haps also in popular philosophy, is the living and conscious individual in whom general forces, truths, or ideas become real, active, efficient forces, truths, and ideas. And the importance of the conception resides in the safeguard thus supposed to arise, which will prevent the realities of the world from being dissipated its measures to circumstances, not tied«down to the inflexible letter of one law in an incoherent and imperfect code. See the Politicus, p. 294 ; Phacdrus, p. 275 ; and compare Aristotle's Wise man whose conduct is not Kara \6yov, but ficra \6yov. 1 See e. g. Encyclopaedia, § 475. xvili.] PHILOSOPHY ON PERSONALITY. 237 away into the endless and restless flux of the terms of thought, 'La bufera infernal che mai non resta.' To such a common frame of mind ideas, truths, forces are vacant, ghostly forms, devoid of true life and reality : to get such they need blood and flesh to clothe them, to give them substance and power. Now Hegel, no less than those who offer this criticism, regards ideas (in the ordinary sense of that term), truths and forces, also as abstractions which need something to make them powers in the real world of nature and the ideal world of mind. Hegel, like Schelling, has a sublime contempt for mere universals. But as to the something else, there is a divergence of view. Two well-known answers are given by the popular philo sophy known as materialism or spiritualism : two systems which are probably not so wide apart as the contrast of their names might imply. According to the former, thinking, ideas, truths, goodness and beauty are special functions (the grosser materialists say secretions) of a special kind of matter— of something which is accessible to ordinary mechanical and chemical tests, but which exhibits also, in certain cases, the exceptional phenomena of consciousness. Here the essential reality is a something, permanent and essen tially indestructible, — something which no man has seen, nor indeed can see, — but which is called Matter. The spiritualistic philosopher (as distinguished from the idealist] regards as the essential realities in the universe what he calls spirits. What these are, also, nobody has as yet (any more than in Kant's time1) given any very authoritative account, but so far as the quasi-scientific expositions in regard to them throw 1 See his ' Dreams of a Spirit-seer, illustrated by Dreams of Meta physics.' (JVerke, ed. Ros. und Schub. Bd. VII. p. 38 sqq.) 238 PROLEGOMENA. [xvui. any general light on the subject, we may say that they suggest only a differently-constituted matter, a matter e. g. of less or more dimensions than that we are most familiar with. Now the advocate of spiritual reality, who protests most strongly against the injury done to personality by reducing it to something fluid and not fixed, something in process and not in persistent substance, seems mostly to lean to a quasi-spiritualistic hypothesis, or to the — so- called — higher materialism. He is an advocate of what we may describe as the soul-thing, of a permanent, (he would even hold, an absolutely permanent) substance or substratum of psychical reality which, no doubt, exhibits certain properties, but is always more than any one, or any mere series of its phenomena. It has been said, indeed, by one who spoke with authority that he that will save his soul shall lose it, and he that will lose it shall find it. But this has always been a hard saying, which has been as far as possible explained away by exegesis. Yet its moral import is not so very far removed from its philosophical equivalent. The true life is not that of self-seeking pleasure, but the life spent in the service of truth and love, the life dedicated to impersonal interests, and ideal good. So also the reality of the human soul as we first know it lies not in itself, but in its transfiguration, its purification, and liberation to higher forms of being. The Soul, in its first avatar in each of us, is after all of the earth, earthy, unless it continue on that path of growth and development on which it has entered. It is as Aris totle said, and said well, the first actualisation J — the 1 It is perilous and misleading (said the ancient Graiae, who dwell on the way to the Hesperides of philosophy) to interpret an old system by the language of modern (and especially German) idealism. It is much worse, replied Perseus, not to interpret it at all, but to xvm.] TnE PERSONAL SOUL. 239 proximate ideality of an organic body. In soul organic body carries out its promise : in soul we, the observers, or untrained psychologists, note our first awareness of mental life in its organic environment. But there are other grades, other heights of achievement, yet set before the principle of life, which is more than mere life and mere soul: or soul contains a germ which must bear higher fruit. To be itself, or to become all that it in promise and potency contains, it must dis possess itself of what clings to it and possess itself of what is its own ; and so transmute its first phase into one more adequate. The soul is, as Hegel has said, the awakening of mind from the sleep of nature1 : it is nature gathering itself out of its absorption in its dis persion, the breath of life and feeling striving through the scattered members of the material world, and find ing itself at first half-asleep, a pervading, unifying current that flows through and makes continuous the various portions of the universe. It is the earliest real, felt unity in which the logical or synthetic pulse— as yet purely potential in Nature, and only surmised by science— re-appears in the actual concrete world. And as the earliest, it is, like first loves, what one clings to hardest as our prime and fundamental differentia. Here at least we are something— a centre of being, and not a mere centreless expanse of extension : something emerging from the world of silence and of night- something in which each feels ' I am not what I see, And other than the things I touch.' And that something we would not lose, at any cost.— But the only way not to lose it, is to use it as a stepping- repeat its magic ipsissima verba,— carefully Latinised, as if they belonged to a cabinet of fossils. 1 Encyclopaedia, §§ 387, 389. 240 PROLEGOMENA. [xvili. stone to higher things. The metaphor, indeed, like metaphors in general, must not be pressed too far. For it is more than a stepping-stone and it is never left behind as a mere dead self: there is ' Nothing of it that doth fade But doth suffer a sea-change Into something rich and strange.' And that richer result into which it is transformed is the consciousness of a self, and the intelligence which wills and knows. If it be asked in what respects the result is richer, the answer is as follows. The soul, — this 'first ente- lechy ' — is exclusive, and it is immersed in its natural limits of organic life. It has yet to go through the school of self-detachment, the process of 'erecting itself above itself* ; and of thus extending its view and its range of control over a wider field of objects. Gradu ally it attains to the rank of a consciousness before which is unrolled the spectacle of a world of objects set over against it, and even of a world within it ; itself as an object deposed to the rank of something to be surveyed. As such, it seems almost to have left all immersion in corporeity completely behind, and to have completely divested itself of any limitation. It floats freely above the real psychical life out of which it emerged — a detached but somewhat shadowy self, not burdened by any restrictions of nature or circum stance. As such a mere Ego, or logical self— as the mere theatre on which the play of ideas takes place, it surveys its real psychical self far below ; it finds itself as a strange sort of thing, and says This was me (which however is not exactly the same as / am I, 1 = I). Yet it was a great step to have thus ceased to be absorbed in its qualities, to be the mere breath of life and feeling, stirring in its several affections and modifi- XVIII.] SUBJECTIVE PERSONALITY. 241 cations. In order to get forward, it was necessary to recoil a little : to save itself— and that must mean to get itself in fuller and richer being — the mind had, as it were, to measure and realise the full depth of its nonentity, and to surrender all that it had hitherto clung to as its own. In an attitude of reflection upon itself it fancies that it is the empty room, the tabula rasa, on which experience is to write itself: but in its secret heart it retains the faith and acts upon it, that it is the power of intelligent and intelligible unity which makes the writing intelligible, if it does not even itself play the writer. What it now seems to find — what fills up its conscious ness, presumed empty and merely receptive, — it gradu ally recognises to be its very and original own. Through labour and experiment it fills up the vacant form (the passive half of itself to which it deposed itself) of consciousness ; and thus, as an intelligent self, a true mind, it has for itself and realises as in itself all the life and reality which in its earlier stage of soul it only was and felt itself naturally to be. But on this stage of free intelligence it is no longer bound up with its natural being in such a way as to feel itself a fixed and restricted centre, sunk in the living environment so as to see no further, and to deem itself in its seclusion the permanent reality, the exclusive fact. It is no longer exclusive and self-concentrated, but inclusive and all-embracing. It is no longer a mere consciousness — a mere receptive and synthetic unity of apperception — but a reason and a mind. And a reason and a mind already refuse to be narrowed and con fined by the same limits as seem appropriate to the soul. In the province of free self-realised intelligence we at least seem to occupy a ground on which others can equally come, — to have nothing peculiar or merely individual. In Knowledge, which is reasoned percep- 242 PROLEGOMENA. [xviil. tion, and in Will, which is reasoned impulse, there is a king's highway, a public forum, where souls meet and converse and perform a collective work ; — and in both mere, i. e. essentially restricted, individuality is at a discount1. Such would be the course of development if we looked at it only in the inwardness or subjectivity of psychical, conscious, and intelligent life. But an analo gous or parallel development may be observed if we look at man as an active, i. e. a practical and moral being, a being who makes Nature his own, stamps it with his title of possession, and who gives to his fellow ship with other souls an objective, outward existence in the forms and institutions of social life. Here too his first achievement is the affirmation of his individuality, the distinction in outward and tangible shape of the Mine from the Thine : the creation of property, and the projection of himself in a world of mutually- recog nised personalities. As the individual soul in the inner life, so the personal being with its property is the solid, insoluble basis of the life in public — the field of social ethics. The same instinct, which in its dread of dissolution clings to the perpetuity of the inner nucleus of soul, upholds the other as containing the stable and eternal security of all social well-being. The immor tality of soul in the inner world : the sacro-sanctity of property in the outer. But if these postulates are to be permitted, if individuality and personality are to abide, they must, in the one case as in the other, bow to the law of development, the law of history and of life. They must correct themselves, re-adjust them selves,— include what they excluded, and re-combine their elements, transmute themselves into what we 1 The above is an attempt to give a very condensed synopsis of Hegel's Philosophy of Mind (Encyclopaedia). XVIII.] OBJECTIVE PERSONALITY. 243 have, after Hegel, called their truth : must redintegrate themselves with suppressed correlatives, and carry out their implications of larger unity. The soul, exclusive and fast-clad in its mere organic vestment, in which it is as yet only the name and form of intellectual life, has first of all to retract itself into the bare abstract con sciousness, or mere self, on which the masses of reality stream, to fill its vacant rooms and empty forms up with ideas. So too the person — that close concretion or coalescence of mind with material — that identification of self with its 'clothes/ its property and all it can vulgarly be said to own, is only an aspect of truth which tends to be over-estimated when it is reflected upon, and must notwithstanding be over-ridden and merged. Withdrawing itself from its clothing of earth and water, and even perhaps from its inner mansion of flesh and bone, personality floats in the free air as the impersonal personality of conscience, — the ethereal realm where pure practical reason rules. In that ether where morals reign absolutely is the home of the categorical imperative, of the Stoical law of duty, of the conscience which, here at least, has might as it has right. It too, like its parallel, consciousness, in the inner mental life, has, or seems to have, all its fulfilment from without. As even Kant admits, it is itself a vacant form ; yet a form of such influence as to impress on whatever comes within its range an obliga tion to be universal and to be uniform. Here too, as in the parallel stage, it was of inestimable importance that mind should, in the socio-ethical sphere, see itself supreme in its innermost dignity and personality,— the personality which lies within, — even though that supremacy were at first no better than as a law, a form, a category, recognised as authoritative and imperative. For conscience, like the field of consciousness, is after R 2 244 PROLEGOMENA. [xvm. all only a quasi-passive self— a remarkable property or endowment, a sort of innate principle or idea by which the mind was seen to be distinguished in a unique way from all things else. To realise once for all the fact that consciousness and conscience form an absolute tribunal from which there can be no appeal : that the ' synthetic unity of apperception ' in the theoretical, and the 'autonomy of the rational wilP in the practical sphere, are the ultimate and final a priori', this is a great thing to do, — even though it only expands and defines the Cartesian principle of clear and distinct ideas, and will remain as Kant's title of honour in the history of philosophy. He thus fenced off or conse crated the sanctuary of the mental and moral life. But it was not enough to set apart the sacred prin ciple, the central hearth-fire of truth and goodness. If at an earlier stage, — earlier, i.e. in this logical analysis, — the formal was wholly sunk in the material, if i. e. the mere series of legal formulae in their hard and brittle outlines were absolutely identified — without doubt or hesitation — with the morally and socially good ; the formal side, or mere spirit and will of good, the abstract principle of morality, is now invested with an equally undue prominence. The actual or concrete ethical community — be it family or state, or other social organ isation — is animated and maintained by a spirit which transcends and includes alike the outward shell of civil law and the inward law of conscience. For, curiously enough, as it may seem at first, both conscience and civil legislation assume the form of imperative and definite commands — laws political or civil, and laws moral. Both fall therefore into an inflexibility, a rigorous and mechanical hardness in their enounce- ments. Both worship the idol of what men call logic, i. e. of formal consistency and formal uniformity, to XVIII.] MORAL PERSONALITY. 245 an excess which sometimes issues in fantastic irregu larities. Their several maxims of legal conformity and of duty for duty's sake are in first appearance excellent: but a further reflection shows that the Law covers a good many inconsistent or at least unrelated laws within its code, and Duty is often sadly to seek in presence of the collisions between what offer themselves as prima facie duties in any given case. The amplest code of laws that ever existed will always leave lots of loop-holes for negligence and villainy, and would never work for an instant, were it not for ever supplemented by the spirit of faith and love, by social piety and political loyalty, by the thousand ties of sentiment and feeling which really vivify its dry bones. So too the abstractions of the conscientious imperative, of the law of duty, of the moral tribunal, of the man within the breast, and of the dignity and beauty of human nature, would effect nothing unless they could always tacitly count on the support of recognised and authoritative social law and usage. Outward rests upon inward ; and rules direct feelings. Here, again, as in the purely intellectual or cognitive sphere, it is evident that the spirit of man has its source of life neither in its abstract self-hood (in consciousness and conscience) nor in its mere natural environment and organic endowment (in sense-affections, and social law and usage), but in the unity of both, — a unity which transcends either. Both individual and society live and grow, because they are continuous and one : because they presuppose an ideal unity or a living Idea at the root of their being, as their inner and essential guiding-principle, at once constitutive and regulative of their action. The machinery of language supplies to the intellectual sphere a sort of sensible meeting-ground and common field in which 246 PROLEGOMENA. [xvm. the development of knowledge becomes possible : and the same purpose is subserved in the social sphere by the machinery of ethical and political forms and institutions. These are the field, the home of freedom, as the other are of knowledge. It is in these collective and objective structures that we get the expression of the law of human development : the visible sign, viz. of the essentially universal nature of the individual. The individual in these attains his relative truth : for they show the weakness of the individuality of the mere individual. They show that his exclusiveness, his quasi-originality, is only an appearance : — confronted, no doubt, by an appearance of an opposite character, as if the originality and the reality lay in the environ ment and the collective body. They point therefore beyond and behind both foci to a common centre or inclusive unity of life. But they do not destroy personality and individuality : they only transform it and made it a more adequate and consistent representation of reality, by giving in it a place to factors or 'moments' which, though always effective, were not recognised as constitutive elements, and treated only as externally interfering agencies. It may be a question, of course, how far it is wise to retain the term after its meaning has thus been altered by expansion and redistribution of elements. On the whole it seems impracticable — and it would be unde sirable, perhaps, even if it were more feasible — to be too hard and fast in our use of denotations. It is hardly the province of philosophy to coin new terms in which to deposit the results of her researches. A term no doubt — particularly if, as the phrase runs, it be luckily discovered, or judiciously selected — may save the ex penditure of thought. But it is hardly the business of philosophy to encourage economy in this direction. xvm.] FORMAL AND REAL. 247 Much more is it the perpetual task of philosophy to counteract the ossification that sets in in terms,— to re-interpret the meaning which is absorbed in these 'counters of thought/ and make them once more sterling money for the market of life. What, for instance, is the work of Aristotle's Ethics, but to set free the genii which the black magic of every-day intercourse has incarcerated in the non-significant Greek term Ew&u/iow'a ? Like our own Happiness, it flits from lip to lip, little better than a mere name, which is still prized, but— except for a few synonyms that are equally vague with itself— is attached to things which a little reflection shows it cannot truly denote. Aristotle seeks— we may say — to define it. But the phrase 'definition* seems barely applicable to the complex process thus implied,— a process of which definition, as ordinarily understood, is only one small portion. For to define happiness, is to reconstruct the conception. Or, to be more accurate, it is really to construct it or reproduce in consciousness its con struction. As it stands, the thing to be defined is a name and a thing, of which certain relations to other things soon begin to show themselves, which is more or less similar to one thing, and more or less to be distinguished from another. To mark it off from these co-terminous things, and to show how they are related to it on different sides,— this would be what we may perhaps call strict, or formal, or nominal, or mere definition. Now whatever be the other uses of such definitions— and they are serviceable at the outgoing in any branch of enquiry,— they are not precisely the work we expect a philosopher to do for us. And assuredly it is not Aristotle who would stop short at that sort of defi nitions. We find accordingly that for the purpose of 248 PR OLE G OMEN A. [xvn I . realising what happiness— the common name for human good_means, he is obliged to bring into the field the whole system of his thought in its cardinal notions of Energy, Soul, &c. Aristotle here as elsewhere re traces the path of thought which carries us from mere, vulgar, inadequately-apprehended happiness (he follows the same process in his treatment of pleasure, friend ship £c.— to take only ethical examples) to true, essential and completely-apprehended happiness, — or, to use Hegel's technical phrases, from happiness as it is an-sich (in or at itself) or as it is fur-sich (for or to itself), to happiness as it is an-und- -fur-sick. In so 'defining' happiness Aristotle is thus obliged to bring in his conceptions of man and of society, of human life and its powers, of natural and acquired faculty, of mind in its relations to nature ; and if not to expound, at least to employ, his fundamental categories of philo sophical thought. Such a machinery can hardly be called less than a construction, i.e. a re-construction by conscious effort of the latent but actual concatenation of the elements in the fact. In this case we traverse the distance which separates mere happiness from true happiness, from happiness imperfectly or abstractly conceived to happiness ade quately and concretely conceived. Of course when we say real or true happiness, we use these terms as they are used within the ordinary range of human speech. An ultimate and absolute in truth and reality is for us at any given time only a comparatively or relatively ultimate and absolute. It is that which, so far as we can see and think (all philosophising pre sumably goes on under this stipulation, tacit or express), gives an expression, an interpretation, a meaning and a construction to reality which leaves no feature un recognised, no contradiction unsolved, no discord XVIII.] FORMAL AND REAL. 249 unreconciled, which leaves nothing outside and alien to it, and suppresses without acknowledgment nothing that has ever been recognised within it. It is, if you like so to call it, the completest, or (if you are really in earnest with your philosophising and have carried it on to what for you is the end) the complete formula of the Absolute — of that which in a transcendent sense is, is all, is the infinite and eternal one. Yet, after all, it is a formula. But here that undying adversary of all thought steps in and says A mere formula. And to that we must here as elsewhere rejoin : No, not a mere formula. A mere formula would be not even a formula, — a formula only in name — and with no reality which it served to formulate. It is a real and true formula, if it be a formula at all, and not some thing which merely swaggers about under that title. Nay more, if it be a true and real formula, it is the truth and the reality in its day and generation, until at least a truer truth and a more real reality shall have been discovered. Let us by all means be modest : but there is a false humility which becomes no man and is the guise of hypocrisy or insincere sincerity. Let us — in other words — never assume that 'we are the men, and that wisdom will die with us' : but equally let us hold fast the faith of reason that what we know as true and real can never be false, i. e. utterly false, however much it may turn out one day to be sur mounted. And, on the other hand, let us equally remember that in the mere and abstract commence ment — the unreal and the untrue, as we must perforce style it by contrast with the (pro tempore) truth and reality — there is no utter and sheer error or unreality. It has always been felt to be one of the most loveable sides of Aristotelianism — this recognition of the reason ableness of all actual fact, or of the truth latent in 250 PROLEGOMENA. [xvin. the honest, though narrow and ill-defined judgments of the mass. Thus, coming back to personality, let us admit that the mere personality which at first sight seemed only worth rejecting, is an element, at least, in true person ality, — or is a part which, because an organic member and no mere mechanical part, is full of traces and indi cations which involve and postulate the whole. The true personality and the true individuality of being is something which presupposes for its completeness the social state — the organic community. It is no doubt familiar to us that, according to an old but never quite dormant view, the collective community is but the aggre gate or congeries of individuals. But the individuals whose aggregation makes the community are themselves products of the social union. Complete, all-round, har monious personality, it is sometimes said, is the highest fruit to be yielded by social development. Or, as the last century would have preferred to put it, the main or sole aim of the State is furtherance towards Humanity —to the stature of the perfect man. And these are true sayings, — but perhaps only half true. If all must grow so that one and each may grow, so and not less must each one grow so that the all— the commonwealth of reason and the kingdom of God — may be more and more present, ' may come.' And that kingdom only comes when All is in Each, and Each is in All : and when, without loss or diminution, each is each and all is all. Then and not till then does personality become true and infinite, free and harmonious individuality, which is in the same instant universality. The monad — to use the language of the great Idealist who did not find individuality at all incompatible with universality —never ceases to be a monad : it is eternal and in destructible, an absolute centre of being. The monad XVIII.] LEIBNIZ ON INDIVIDUALITY. 251 in its individual measure ' expresses ' or ' envelops ' the Infinite or Absolute: it is, i.e. under a subjective limi tation, identical with the absolute, a concentration or condensation of it into an impenetrable, i. e. literally an individual, point,— but a point which is in the psychical or intellectual world never entirely carens recordatione, or oblivious of its essential totality. But if the monad ' expresses ' the Absolute, it no less concords or sym pathises in harmonious development with all its con geners, the other monads : so that while it neither interferes with them, nor suffers violence from them, it yet exists and acts in an ideal identity, that is, in a real fellowship, with them. Again, the monad has what may be called its side of passivity, but passivity here does not mean mere passivity, but rather the essential limitation due to its special and peculiar stand-point — a limitation which in the higher orders of being becomes transparent or is transcended. How far Leibniz succeeds in recon ciling this apparent contradiction — how far even any one can reveal the mystic indwelling of universal and indi vidual in each other, this is a serious question in its place : but it is only bare justice to Leibniz to say that he at least never failed to emphasise both aspects of reality, and that if one ' moment ' is predominant and fundamental in his work it is not the monad, but the Monad of Monads. If necessity be the right word to express the relation of the Universal Law to the individual being and to affirm that the individual is not a loose self-supporting unit (and Leibniz, far from think ing so, always uses in its stead the phrase inclinat, non nccessitat1 , to emphasise the immanence of law, or the autonomy of every completed being), then Leibniz is not 1 See especially in the Theodicee, part I. § 43 seqq. Cf. Nouv. Ess. II. § 9, incline sans necessiter: I. § 13, La ntccssite ne doit pas etre con- fondue avec la determination. 252 PROLEGOMENA. [xvm. less, but more necessitarian than Spinoza. His differ ence from Spinoza, in fact, lies mainly, if not solely, in his clearer recognition of the transcendence, no less than the immanence, of the Absolute, which Spinoza has somewhat veiled under the apparent insignificance of the difference between natura naturans and natura naturata. Yet the Monad of Monads is no supra- mundane, or merely transcendent God. But if we further ask whether such personality is attainable in the world of experience and describable in terms of thought — whether there be any actual and visible agent possessed of this true personality, as we have agreed to call it, we are in face with a higher stage of the problem of personality. And that question in other words brings us back to where we began. A true and real personality, a complete individuality is something which so transmutes all that we are most accustomed to call by that name that it is hardly any use clinging to it, unless to protest against the danger of mistaking such expansion and transmutation to be only a blank negation. Yet to cling to it too much involves a danger for the true recognition of that transcendent's univer sality. All human personality, all natural individuality is, as Lotze has eloquently pointed out l, something which falls far short of what it professes to be. But in the general failure to unite the universal with the particular, or the fact with the idea, there are degrees ; and we can at least affirm so much as this that the truest individuality and the most real personality is not that which is least permeated by thought, but that in which thought has had the largest share. Individuality is something more than a mere sum of general qualities; — that is certainly the fact ; but it is not less the fact, that for us an individuality and personality is more perfect 1 Microcosmus, Book IX. chap. 4. xvill.] LIMITS OF PERSONALITY. 253 and true in proportion as more general function and universal character coalesce into harmony and power in it. Assert then the initial presence and virtue of individuality and personality in the human soul : but remember that it has this virtue, not for what it is, but for what it promises and may reasonably be expected to be, and that, to realise the promise, it has to behave inclu sively, rather than exclusively, gather up into itself and make its own all content, rather than set itself up in reserve and isolation. We have seen that the social organisation, animated as it is by the moral idea, is rather the arena on which the true union of mind and matter, of idea and nature, of thought and fact may be worked for, than itself the fruition of such an effort. All-important is the State ; all-important the ethical idea which pervades it. But the world of freedom — the ideal world so far made actual — is not what it promised to be. ' Is it not/ said Plato, ' the nature of things that the actual should always lack the perfection of theory ? ' In the visible world the State, indeed, rules supreme : ' it is/ as Hegel might say in the words of his great predecessor in political theory, ' that Leviathan or mortal God to whom under the immortal God we owe our welfare and safety.' But there is something in the State which the State in its palpable reality cannot adequately express. If it is highest in the hierarchy of this world, the lowest in the ideal kingdom of the Absolute is higher than it. Above the State as the embodiment and the guarantee of the moral life, there is the realm of Art, Religion, and Philosophy. In them man's craving for individuality and personality finds a satisfaction it could never hope for below them : they at least restore the truth and reality of man's life and of the universe in a measure far exceeding what even morality could do. 254 PROLEGOMENA. [xvin. If we ask then what Art, Religion, and Science have to show of Personality or true realised individuality, the answer is briefly as follows. Had it not been that august names have spoken of imitation as the essence of Art-work, we should hardly have deemed it possible that men should speak of Realistic Art. Yet here, as in Religion and in Science, the epithet is introduced to guard against a misconception of the province of Idealism. All Art, all Religion, all Science, are and must be idealistic : but they can never be — as the familiar phrase puts it — merely idealistic, i. e. visionary, fantastic, unreal. All of them, in other words, may be said to show us ' the light that never was on sea or land ' — the heavenly city — the eternal truth of things. But they must, on their peril, show it here and now, and not in a pretended or other world. They must — no less than law and morality — work in terrestrial materials, and not with superfine celestialities. Mentem mortalia tan- gunt. It is out of the oldest and commonest realities of life and death that the poet and the painter make the melodies of heaven sound in our ears, and gladden us with the rays of the empyrean. It is out of the hard rock of the real that the artist's rod must strike the well- spring of the ideal. So too, in like manner, a religion must show the Divine, but show Him immanent : an immanence which, on one hand, shall not drag Godhead down to the level of casual reality, nor on the other set Him far off in lonely transcendence. The aesthetic faculty, awakened as it is by the natural response of man's perceptions to the harmonies of existence, to the spontaneous coherency of its many parts in a united whole, and stimulated by the creative work of human art, which moulds even the naturally discordant or unconnected into a concordant expression (sometimes it may be, as in handicraft, only to satisfy XVIII.] PERSONALITY IN ART. 255 human needs), lifts us above the imperfections and fragmentariness of things, above our selfish interest in them, into a frame of mind where they are seen whole and perfect, and yet one and veritably individual. In its supreme or comprehensive phase it does not deal merely with the beautiful, nor merely with the beautiful and sublime. All true art, whether it awakes awe or admiration, laughter or tears, whether it melts the soul, or steels it to endurance, has a common characteristic ; and that is to raise the single instance, the prosaic or commonplace fact, into its universal, eternal, infinite significance. It frees the fact from the limitations which our distractions, our practicality, our temporary hopes and fears, have deeply stamped upon it. It is still, after art has dealt with it, to all appearance a single fact : but it now has the universe behind it and within it. It carries us away from the incompleteness, the pressure of externals, the solicitude for the future and the regrets for the past, into a self-contained, self-satisfying totality, into freedom and leisure, rest which is not stolid, and action which involves no toil. Such a result is partly, as was said, the gift of common nature, which speaks peace, comfort, joy, self-possessed fruition for all her children when their sense is open and free : partly it comes through those select ones among these children who have a larger perception of the meaning and inner truth of her works, and who can by a sensible recon struction, which if it is fair and successful will only bring out more clearly the unity and harmony which deeper insight detects, help others to see and enjoy what they have felt and rejoiced over. Such are the poets — in the widest sense — the makers, the seers, who in verse, in music, in picture and sculpture — who, in human lives, it may be even in the conduct of their own, show us how divine a thing is nature and 256 PROLEGOMENA. [xvm. humanity : show "us the secret and unheard harmonies that to the full-opened ear absorb and transmute the lower discords of life and vulgar reality. It is they who give immortality and divinity, who make heroes and demigods *. Or, if they may not be said to make them, they half-reveal and half-construct the ideal figures which stand high and beneficent in the history of the world. And by those who thus half-construct, and half- reveal, are meant not merely the single artists in whom the process culminates to final outline and publicity, but the many-voiced poesy of the collective human heart which out of its myriad elemental springs constitutes the total figure, the august image of the hero, and the saint, lending him from its plenitude all that his abstract self seemed to want. It is on the tide of national and human enthusiasm that the individual artist is lifted up to realise the full significance of his ideal figure, and his imaginative craft can only be inspired by the vigour and warmth of the collective passion for noble ends and high action. Nowhere it would seem is the ideal of personality and many-sided individuality more adequately realised. Here, at last, the whole truth of life, the indwelling of individual and universal in one body, seems to be realised. But it is realised in an ideal. It is — if we analyse it — a synthesis of three elements ; partly in the material reality which serves as bodily vehicle ; partly in the conception and technique of the artist ; partly in the general mind which inspires both the material and the form with its own larger life. It is — as its name implies — an artificial product — a synthesis of elements which tend to fall apart. Technique varies, conceptions lose their interest, the tone of general culture alters, 1 See the well-known passage in Wilhelm Meistjrs Lehrjahre, Book II. chap. 2. XVIIL] IDEAL PERSONALITY. 257 and materials are dependent on locality. When that happens, the work of art is left high and dry : no longer a living God, but a dead idol, still wondrous, but speak ing no more its human language. So it is with the heroic figures who rise into the purer air of universal history. They also— so far as they live with a personal power — are works of art : works of real-idealism. For all history which deserves the name, and is not mere abstract dry-as-dust chronicle (as to the possibility of which utter aridity there may be legitimate doubts), is a work of fiction or invention, of reconstruction. It seeks to understand its characters. But to understand them it is not (and as historical art cannot be) content with a mere reference to motives acting on them from outside. It seeks to understand them with and in their times — to see in them the full measure of contemporary life and thought which elsewhere has found so meagre expression. Such is the artistic completion of personality in the ideal, — whether in what is called history, or what is called art. It exaggerates a truth, because it loses sight of the background. And that background, which helps to con stitute such ideal personality, is no constant element. The centuries and generations as they roll contribute their varying quota to set, as they say, the historical character in its true light, in its fulness and truth of reality. And thus this personality of the great leaders of human life is only an image and a sign— a fruit of development, no bare fact which remains unchanged and always the same. It is rather a personification than a personality. It incarnates the living spirit who is universal and eternal in the limits of a sensuously- defined individual, and indeed incarnates there only so much as the generation it speaks to can see of complete truth. It is only after all a vehicle of truth ; though s 258 PROLEGOMENA. [xvill. a nobler vehicle than social and personal ethics can afford. As it is felt that the treasure of the idea— that the full power of spiritual life — cannot be adequately stored in the earthen vessels of mortality, the consummation of personality is forced to recede into the invisible if it would be still conceived as attainable. ' True person ality/ says Lotze, Ms with the Infinite.' What here is fragmentary, is there a rounded total, a perfect unity : He alone is absolutely self-determining, self-explain ing : is all that He means to be, and means all that He is. In a sense, philosophy does not hesitate to counter sign all this. But, in adopting it, philosophy must reserve the right of noting the danger and the am biguity of such language. Religion does well, philo sophy may say, in thus insisting upon the dependence of all appearance on one Absolute reality ; but it is well also not to forget that all appearance is also the appear ance of that reality or Absolute. And in so saying, be it added, philosophy assumes no essential superiority to religion. Religion in its fulness, and apart from any theories that may grow up under its wing, is more than theory, more than mere philosophy: it is the consum mating unity of life — the enthusiasm and supreme power of life, its consecration and divinisation by its assured immanence in the eternal and universal. It is, in short, as was long ago said of it, the true life, the light which is the light and life of men ; and its inspiring principles are faith, hope, and love. But when unas sisted religion proceeds to set before itself the meaning and lesson of its life, when it proceeds to formulate a theory of the world and set out a scheme of world- history, it trespasses on the field of knowledge, and is amenable to the criticisms of the reflective spirit — the spirit of philosophy. And that criticism briefly is to the xvm.] DIVINE PERSONALITY. 259 effect that the religious theory in its ordinary form is an imperfect interpretation of the religious experience. Nor is this to derogate from the prerogative of the friends of God. It is only to criticise the formulae and phrases of dogmatic theology — a theology, however, which is as old as religion itself, and which takes different forms from age to age, and from one level of thought to another, always in its measure translating religious reality, truth, or experience into the categories, na'ive or artificial, simple or complex, of the science (it may be the pseudo-science) of the time. Philosophy, therefore, is the criticism of the science of God — that is of theology — as it is the criticism of other sciences. For criticism philosophy always is : always the reflec tion upon fixed dogma, and the discussion of it till it becomes sensible of its defects, and stands upon another and higher plane. And to some it may seem that this is the sole function which philosophy can legitimately undertake. 'Yet,' as Aristotle remarked, 'the good critic must know what he criticises/ He must not merely reflect upon it from outside, but deal with it from the plenitude of experience, from the abundance of the heart. If he be a critic then, he cannot be a mere critic, but also an agent in the work of reconstruction. Or, if we put the thing otherwise; though, as Fichte said (p. 28), philosophy is a different thing from life, the true philosopher can never be a mere philosopher, but must, if he is to reach the height of his vocation, have also entered into the full experience of reality, into the whole truth of life. His philosophy will then not be outside of religion and aesthetic perception. In its comprehension of all grades and forms of reality and truth, goodness, holiness, beauty, will have their place. He also will be among the theologians. s 2 260 PROLEGOMENA. And when the philosopher deals with personality in this high, this supreme sphere, he will submit that the truth of personality is subordinate to the truth of spiri tuality. He will argue that by sticking too closely and fixedly to personality we are running a risk of bringing down the divine to the level of the human. If, with Dante, he can say that in its very heart the Light Eternal ' Mi parve pinta della nostra effige ;' he will undoubtedly add with Dante ' Oh quanto e corto '1 dire e come fioco Al mio concetto ;' or, with the first philosophical theologian who inter preted the experience of Christian life, he will rise from the historical Jesus to the inward witness of the Spirit. CHAPTER XIX. GENESIS IN MENTAL LIFE. ARISTOTLE, who saw into the nature of abstract entities, remarked that the mind was nothing before it exercised itself1. The mind,— and the same will turn out true of many things else where it is at first unsurmised;— is not a fixed thing, a sort of exceedingly refined substance, which we can lay hold of without further trouble. It is what it has become, or what it makes itself to be. This point, that 'To be'^'To have become,' or rather to have made itself, is an axiom never to be lost sight of in dealing with the mind. It is easy to talk of and about conscience and freewill, as if these were existing things in a sort of mental space, as hard to miss or mistake as a stone and an orange, or as if they were palpable organs of mind, as separately observable as the eye or ear. One asks if the will is free or not, as glibly as one might ask whether an orange is sweet; and the answer can be given with equal ease, affirmatively or negatively, in both cases. Everything in these cases depends on whether the will has made itself free or not, whether indeed we are speaking of the will at all, and on what we mean by freedom. To ask the question in an abstract way, taking no account of circumstances, is one of those 1 De Anima, iii. 4. 262 PROLEGOMENA. temptations which lead the intellect astray and pro duce only confusion and wordy war — as a good deal of so-called popular metaphysics has done. The mind and its phenomena, as they are called, cannot be dis sected with the same calmness of analysis as other substances which adapt themselves to the scalpel : nor is dissection after all more than a part of the scientific process, subject to the control of the synthesis in physiology. The ordinary metaphysician makes his own task easy and his thoughtful reader's a burden, by plunging too lightly in medias res. He wants patience— often, per haps, because he thinks too much of his reader's impatience at analysis — to unravel the tangled mass which human experience, when first looked at, presents. He is apt to catch at any end which promises to effect a temporary clearance. True philosophy, on the con trary, must show that it has got hold of what it means to discuss : it has to construct its subject-matter : and it constructs it by tracing every step and movement in its construction shown in actual history. The mind is what it has been made and has made itself; and to see what it is we must consider it not as an Alpha and Omega of research, as popular conception and language tend to represent it, but in the stages constituting its process, in the fluidity of its development, in the elements out of which it results. We must penetrate the apparent fixity and simplicity under which it comes forward, and see through it into the process which bears it into being. For, otherwise, the object of our investigation is taken, as if it were the most unmis takable thing of sense and fancy, — as if everybody were agreed that this and no other were the point in question. But in this matter of stability and the reverse, there xix.] NATURAL AND MENTAL EVOLUTION. 263 is a broad distinction between the natural and the spiritual world. In Nature every step in the organisa tion, by which the Cosmos is developed, has an inde pendent existence of its own : and the lowest formation confronts the highest, each standing by itself beside the other. Matter and motion, for example, are not merely found as subordinate elements entering into the making of a plant or an animal. They have a free existence of their own : and the free existence of matter in motion is seen in the shape of the planetary system. So, too, chemical or electrical phenomena can be observed by themselves, operating in spheres where they are untrammeled by the influence of biological conditions. It seems, at least at first sight, to be different in the case of mind. There the specific types or several stages in the integrating process of mental development seem to have no substantive existence in the earlier part of the range, and to appear only as states or factors entering into, and merged in, the higher grades of development. This causes a peculiar difficulty in the study of mind. We cannot seize a formation in an independent shape of its own : we must trace it in the growth of the whole. Mental fusion and coalescence of elements is peculiarly close, and hardly leaves any traces of its constituent factors \ 1 A philological parallel may make this clearer. 'The Indo- German,' says Misteli (Typen des Spmchbaucs, p. 363), 'embraces or condenses several categories in a single idea in a way which though less logical is more fruitful ; for in this way he procures graspable totals with which he can work further, and not patch-work which would crumble away in his hands. Our He includes four grammatical categories, which work not separately, but as a whole :— third person, masculine gender, singular, nominative ; whereas the Magyar o is the vehicle only of one category, the third person, which is either determined as singular by the context, or as plural by the addition of k: gender in these languages does not exist : and as sub ject again o is specially interpreted from the context. The unification 264 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. Sensation, for instance, in its purity, as mere sensation, is apparently something which we can never study in isolation. All the sensation which we can, in the strictly psychological (as opposed to the physiological) mode of study, examine, i. e. which we can reproduce in ourselves, is more than mere sensation : it includes elements of thought, and probably of desire and will. This, of course, makes the difficulties of so-called intro spection : difficulties so great and real that they have provoked in natural reaction a set against introspection altogether, and the adoption of the external observation (physiological or so-called psycho-physical) employed in the ' objective ' sciences. And hence when we accept the name, such as intellect, conscience, will, &c., as if it expressed something specially existent in a detached shape of its own, we make an assumption which it is impossible to justify. We are reckoning with paper- money which belongs to no recognised currency, and may be stamped as the dealer wills. The consequence is that the thing with which we begin our examination is an opaque point, — a mere terminus a quo, from which we start on our journey of explication, leaving the terminus itself behind us unexplained. The constituents of mind do not lie side by side tranquilly co-existent, like the sheep beside the herbage on which it browses. Their existence is maintained in an inward movement, by which, while they differentiate themselves, they still keep up an identity. In our investigations we cannot begin with what is to be defined. The botanist, if he is to give us a science of the plant, must begin with something whose indwelling aim it is to be itself and to realise its own possibility. of the four categories makes He an individual and a word ; the generality and isolation of one category makes o an abstract and a stem.' XI*-] MIND AS A GROWTH. 265 He must begin with what is not the plant, and end with what is ; begin, let us say, with the germ which has the tendency to pass into the plant. The speculative science of biology begins with a cell, and builds these cells up into the tissues and structures out of which vegetables and animals are constituted. The object of the science appears as the result of the scientific process: or, a science is the ideal construction of its object. As in these cases, so in the case of thought. We must see it grow up from its simplest element, from the bare point of being, the mere speck of being which, if actually no better than nothing, is yet a germ which in the air of thought will grow and spread ; and see it appear as a result due to the ingrowing and outgrowing union of many elements, none of which satisfies by itself, but leads onward from abstractions to the meeting of abstractions in what is more and more concrete. The will and conscience, understanding and reason, of man are not matter-of-fact units to be picked up and exam ined. You must, first of all, make sure what you have in hand : and to be sure of that is to see that the mind is the necessary outcome of a course of development. The mind is not an immediate datum, with nothing behind it, coming upon the field of mental vision with a divinely-bestowed array of faculties ; but a mediated unity, i. e. a unity which has grown up through a com plex interaction of forces, and which lives in differences through comprehending and reconciling antagonisms. If the mind be not thus exhibited in its process, in the sum and context of its relations, we may mean what we like with each mental object that comes under our observation: but with as much right another observer may mean something else. We may, of course, define as we please : we may build up succes sive definitions into a consistent total : but such a 266 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. successful arrangement is not a real science. Unless we show how this special form of mind is constituted, we are dealing with abstractions, with names which we may analyse, but which remain as they were when our analysis is over, and which seem like unsubstantial ghosts defying our coarse engines of dissection. They are not destroyed : like immaterial and aery beings they elude the sword which smites them, and part but to re-unite. The name, and the conception bodied forth in it, is indeed stagnant, and will to all appear ance become the ready prey of analysis : but there is something behind this materialised and solidified con ception, this worn-out counter or sign, which mere analysis cannot even reach. And that underlying nature is a process or movement, a meeting of ele ments, which it is the business of philosophy to unfold. The analyst in this case has dealt with ideas as if they were a finer sort of material product, a fixed and assail able point : and this is perhaps the character of the generalised images, which take the place of thoughts in our customary habits of mind. But ideas, when they have real force and life, are not hard and solid, but, as it were, fluid and transparent, and can easily escape the divisions and lines which the analytical intellect would impose. Perhaps some may think that it is unwise to fight with ghosts like these, and that the best plan would be to disregard this war of words alto gether. But, on the other hand, it may be urged that such unsubstantial forms have a decided reality in life : that men will talk of them and conjure by their means, with or without intelligence ; and that the best course is to understand them. It will then be seen that it is our proper work as philosophers to watch the process, by which the spiritual unity divides and yet retains its divided members in unity. XIX.] ANALYSIS AND SYNTHESIS. 267 Even in the first steps we take to get a real hold of an object we see this. To understand it, we must deprive it of its seeming independence. Every indi vidual object is declared by the logician to be the meeting of two currents, the coincidence of two move ments. It concentrates into an undecompounded unit, —at least such it appears to representative or material thought,— two elements, each of which it is in turn identifiable with. The one of these elements has been called the self-same (or identity), the universal, the genus, the whole : while the second is called the differ ence, the particular, the part. And by these two points of reference it is fixed,— by two points which are for the moment accepted as stationary. What has thus "been stated in the technical language of Logic is often repeated in the scientific parlance of the day, but with more materialised conceptions and in more concrete cases. The dynamic theory of matter represents it as a unity of attraction and repulsion. A distinguished Darwinian remarks that 'all the various forms of organisms are the necessary products of the uncon scious action and reaction between the two properties of adaptability and heredity, reducible as these are to the functions of nutrition and reproduction V The terms ' action and reaction ' are hardly sufficient, it may be, to express the sort of unity which is called for : but the statement at least shows the reduction of an actual fact to the interaction of two forces, the meeting of two currents. The one of these is the power of the kind, or universal, which tends to keep things always the same : the other the power of localised circumstances and particular conditions, which tends to render things more and more diversified. The one may be called a centripetal, the other a centrifugal force. If the one 1 Hackel, Nattirliche Schopfungs-Geschichtc, p. 157. 268 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. be synthetic, the other is analytic. But such names are of little value, save for temporary distinction, and must never be treated as permanent differences which explain themselves. The centre is relative, and so is the totality. Thus it is that the so-called Evolutionist explains the origin of natural kinds. They are what they severally are by reason of a process, a struggle, by alliances and divisions, by re-unions and selections. They are not independent of the inorganic world around them : it has entered into their blood and structure, and made them what they are. To understand them we must learn all we can of the simpler and earlier forms, which have left traces in their structure : traces which, without the existence of such more primitive forms, we might have misunderstood, or have passed by unperceived. And, again, we learn that our hard and fast distinctions are barely justified by Nature. There, kind in its extreme examples seems to run into kind, and we do not find the logically-exact type accurately embodied anywhere. Our classifications into genera and species turn out to be in the first instance prompted by a practical need to embrace the variety in a simple shape. But though perfectly valid, so far as we use them for such ends, they tend to lead us false, if we press them too far. And when we have seen so much, we may learn the further lesson that the variety of organisation, animal and vegetable, is only the exhibition in an endless detail by single pictures, more or less complementary, more or less inclusive of each other, of that one vital organisa tion in principle and construction which we could not otherwise have had presented to us. In a million lessons from the vast ranges of contemporary and of extinct life there is impressed upon the biological observer the idea of that system of life-function and life-structure XIX.] MENTAL AND NATURAL EVOLUTION. 269 which is the goal of biological science. The interest in the mere variety whether of modern or of primeval forms of life is as such merely historical ; its truer use is to enable the scientific imagination to rise above local or temporary limitations. And thus in the end the records and guesses of evolution in time and place serve to build up a theory of the timeless universal nature of life and organisation. And what is true of Nature is equally true of the Mind. For these two, as we have already seen, are not isolable from each other. Neither the mind nor the so-called external world are either of them self-subsistent existences, issuing at once and ready-made out of nothing. The mind does not come forth, either equipped or un-equipped, to conquer the world : the world is not a prey prepared for the spider, waiting for the mind to comprehend and appropriate it. The mind and the world, the so-called 'subject' and so-called 'object/ are equally the results of a process: and it is only when we isolate the terminal aspects of that process, and in the practical business of life forget the higher theoretical point of view, that we lose sight of their origin, and have two worlds facing each other. As the one side or aspect of the process gathers feature and form, so does the other. As the depth and inten sity of the intellect increases, the limits of the external world extend also. For the psychical life is just the power which maintains a continuing correlation between the body and its environment, and between the various elements in that environment. It is the unity in which that correlation lives and is aware of itself. It is the subject-object, which sets one element against another, and gives it quasi-independence. The mind of the savage is exactly measured by the world he has around him. The dull, almost animal, sensation and 270 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. feeling, which is what we may call his mental action, is just the obverse of the narrow circumference that girdles his external world. The beauty and interest of the grander phenomena of terrestrial nature, and of the celestial movements, are ideally non-existent for a being, whose whole soul is swallowed up in the craving for food, the fear of attack, and the lower enjoyments of sense. In the course of history we can see the intellect growing deeper and broader, and the limits of the world recede simultaneously with the advance of the mmd. This process or movement of culture takes place in the sequence of generations, and in the variety of races and civilisations spread over the face of the world. But here too, the higher science, not resting in the merely historical inquiry, takes no interest in the medium of time, and merely uses it to supply material for the rational sequence of ideas *. The objective world of knowledge is really at one with the subjective world : they spring from a common source, what Kant called the 'original synthetic unity of apperception/ The distinction between them flows from abstraction, from failure to keep in view the whole round of life and experience. The subjective world — the mind of man — is really constituted by the same force as the objective world of nature : the latter has been translated from the world of extension, with its externality of parts in time and space, into an inner world of thought where unity, the fusion or coalescence of all types and forms, is the leading feature. The difficulty of passing from the world of being to the world of thoughts, from notion to thing, from subject to object, from Ego to Non-ego, is a difficulty which men have unduly allowed to grow upon them. It grows by talking of and analysing mere being, mere thought, 1 See above, pp. 155, 198. XIX.] BEING AND THOUGHT. 271 mere notion, or mere thing. And it will be dispelled when it is seen that there is no mere being, and no mere thought : that these two halves of the unity of ex perience — the unity we divide and the division we unify in every judgment we make— are continually leaning out of themselves, each towards the other. But men, beginning as they must from themselves, and failing to revise and correct their stand-point till it became an dpxf) ai/uTro&Tor, argued from a belief that the individual mind was a fixed and absolute centre, from which the universe had to be evaluated. In Hegel's words, they made man and not God the object of their philosophy1. So that Kant really showed the outcome of a system which acted on the hypothesis that man in his indi vidual capacity was all in all. Hegel, on his own showing, came to prove that the real scope of philo sophy was God ;— that the Absolute is the ' original synthetic unity' from which the external world and the Ego have issued by differentiation, and in which they return to unity. If this be so, then there is behind the external world and behind the mind an organism of pure types or forms of thought, — an organism which presents itself, in a long array of fragments, to the senses in the world of nature, where all things lie outside of one another, and which then is, as it were, reflected back into itself so as to constitute the mind, or spiritual world, where all parts tend to coalesce in a more than organic unity. The deepest craving of thought, and the fundamental problem of philosophy, will accordingly be to discover the nature and law of that totality or primeval unity,— the totality which we see appearing in the double aspect of nature and mind, and which we first become acquainted with as it is manifested in this state of dis- 1 Hegel's Werke, vol. i. p. 15. 272 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. union. To satisfy this want is what the Logic of Hegel seeks. It lays bare the kingdom of those potent shades, — the phases of the Idea — which embodies itself more concretely in the external world of body, and the inward world of mind. The psychological or individualist con ditions, which even in the Kantian criticism sometimes seem to set up mind as an entity parallel to the objects of nature, and antithetic to nature as a whole, have fallen away. Reason has to be taken in the whole of its actuali- sation as a world of reason, not in its bare possibility, not in the narrow ground of an individual's level of develop ment, but in the realised formations of reasonable know ledge and action, as shown in Art and Life, Science and Religion. In this way we come to a reason which might be in us or in the world, but which, being to a certain extent different from either, was the focus of two orders of manifestations. To ascertain that ultimate basis of the world and mind was the chief thing philosophy had to see to. But in order to do this, a good deal of preliminary work was necessary. The work of Logic, as understood by Hegel, involves a stand-point which is not that of every-day life or reflection on experience. It presupposes the whole process from the provisional starting-point which seems at first sight simplest and universally acceptable, upwards to the unhypothetical principle which — though at a long distance — it involves and leads up to, or pre supposes. We all know Aristotle's dictum 'Ei/ rots alaOrjTo'is ra I'orjrd e'orif : Nihil IH intcllectu quod HOH priUS 111 sensu. The fact of sense and feeling is the fact of ex perience : or rather the fact and reality of experience is the underlying truth which the expression of it in terms of sense and perception inadequately interprets. Even in the principles of sensation there is judgment, thought, reasoning : but it needs eliciting, re-statement, xix.] HEGEL'S PHENOMENOLOGY, 273 opening up, and explanation. The Phenomenology of Mind is, as Hegel himself has said, his voyage of dis covery. It traces the path, and justifies the work of traversing it, from the ill-founded and imperfect cer tainties of sense and common-sense, up through various scientific, moral, and religious modes of interpreting experience and expressing its net sum of reality, till it culminates in the stand-point of 'pure thought/ of supreme or ' absolute ' consciousness. It is certainly not a history of the individual mind : and equally little is it a history of the process of the intellectual development of the race. In a way it mixes up both. For its main interest is not on the purely historical side. It indulges in bold transitions, in sudden changes of scene from ancient Greece and Rome to modern Germany, from public facts and phases of national life to works of fiction (compare its use of Goethe's Faust and his version of Rameau's Nephew}. It lingers — for historical accuracy and pro portion unduly— over the period of Kant and Fichte, and reads Seneca by the light of the Sorrows of Wcrther. For its aim is to gather from the inspection of all ways in which men have attempted to reach reality the indication of their several content of truth, and of the several defects from it, so as to show the one necessary path on which even all their errors converge and which they serve to set out in clearer light. Hegel's philosophy is undoubtedly the outcome of a vast amount of historical experience, particularly in the ancient world, and implies a somewhat exhaustive study of the products of art, science, politics, and re ligion. By experience he was led to his philosophy, not by what is called a priori reasoning. It is curious indeed to observe the prevalent delusion that German philosophy is the ' high priori road,' — to hear its pro fundity admired, but its audacity and neglect of obvious 274 PROLEGOMENA. [xix. facts deplored. The fact is that without experience neither Hegel nor anybody else will come to anything. But, on the other hand, experience is in one sense only the yet undeciphered mass of feeling and reality, the yet unexpounded psychical content of his life ; or, taken in another acceptation, it is only a form which in one man's case means a certain power of vision, and in another a different degree. One man sees the idea which explains and unifies experience as actuality : to the other man it is only a subjective notion. And even when it is seen, there are differences in the subsequent development. One man sees it, asserts it on all hands, and then closes. Another sees it, and asks if this is all, or if it is only part of a system. An appeal to 'my ex perience ' is very much like an appeal to 4 my senti ments ' or ' my feelings ' : it may prove as much or as little as can be imagined : in other words, it can prove nothing. The same is true of the appeal to conscious ness, that oracle on whose dicta it has sometimes been proposed to found a system of philosophy. By that name seems meant the deliverances of some primal and unerring nucleus of mind, some real and central self, whose voice can be clearly distinguished from the mere divergent cries of self-interest and casual opinion. That such discernment is possible no philosophy will seek to deny : but it is a discernment which involves comparison, examination, and reasoning. And in that case the appeal to consciousness is the exhortation to clear and deliberate thinking. While, on another side, it hints that philosophy does not — in the end- deal with mere abstractions, but with the real concrete life of mind. And if an appeal to other people's experi ence is meant, that is only an argument from authority. What other people experience is their business, not mine. Experience means a great deal for which it is XIX.] HEGEL'S PHENOMENOLOGY. 275 not the right name : and to give an explanation of what it is, and what it does, would render a great service to English methodologists. There are, however, two modes in which these studies to discover the truth may appear. In the one case they are reproduced in all their fragmentary and patch-work character. They are supposed to possess a value of their own, and are enunciated with all the detail of historic incident. The common-place books of a man are, as it were, published to instruct the world and give some hint of the extent of his reading. But, in the other case, the scaffolding of incident and externality may be removed. The single facts, which gave the persuasion of the idea, are dismissed, as in teresting only for the individual student on his way to truth : or, if the historical vehicle of truth be retained at all, it is translated into another and intellectual medium. Such a history, the quintessence of extensive and deep research, is presented in the Phenomenology. The names of persons and places have faded from the record, as if they had been written in evanescent inks,— dates are wanting, — individualities and their biographies yield up their place to universal and timeless principles. Such typical forms are the concentrated essence of end less histories. They remind one of the descriptions which Plato in his Republic gives of the several forms of temporal government. Or, to take a modern instance, the Hegelian panorama of thought which presents only the universal evolution of thought, — that evolution in which the whole mind of the world takes the place of all his children, whether they belong to the common level, or stand amongst representative heroes, — may be paralleled to English readers by Browning's poem of Sordello. There can be no question that such a method is exposed to criticism, and likely to excite T 2 276 PROLEGOMENA. misconception. If it tend to give artistic completeness to the work, it also tantalises the outsider who has a desire to reach his familiar standing-ground. He wishes a background of time and space, where the forms of the abstract ideas may be embodied to his mind's eye. In most ages, and with good ground, the world has been sceptical, when it perceived no reference to authorities, no foot-notes, no details of experiments made : nor is it better disposed to accept provisorily, and find, as the process goes on, that it verifies itself to intelligence. CHAPTER XX. GENERAL LAW OF THE PHILOSOPHY OF HISTORY. ' THE order and concatenation of ideas/ says Spinoza, ' is the same as the order and concatenation of things V The objective world at least of acts and institutions develops parallel with the growth and system of men's ideas. In the tangled skein which human life and reality present to the observer, the only promising clue is to be found in the process by which in histor^he past throws light on the present and gets light in return. There in the stream of time and in the expanses of space the condensed results, the hard knots, which present life offers for explanation, are broken up into a vast number of problems, each pre senting a different aspect, and one helping towards a fairer and clearer appreciation of another. The present medium of general intelligence and theory in which we live embraces in a way the results of all that has preceded it, 01 all the steps of culture through which '.'-e world has rLen. But in this body of intellectual be* ofs and ideas with which our single soul is clad,— in ihis common soil of thought,— the several contributions of the past have been half or even wholly obliterated, and are only the shadows of their old selves. What in a former day was a question of all-engrossing interest has left but a trace : the complete 1 Eth. ii 7. 278 PROLEGOMENA. [xx. and detailed formations of ancient thought have lost their distinctness of outline, and have shrunk into mere shadings in the contour of our intellectual world. Questions, from which the ancient philoso phers could never shake themselves loose, are now only a barely perceptible nuance in the complex questions of the present day. Discussions about the bearings of the 'one' and the 'many/ puzzles like those of Zeno, and the casuistry of statesmanship such as is found in the Politics of Aristotle, have for most people little else than an antiquarian interest. We scarcely detect the faint traces they have left in the 'burning questions' of our own age. We are too ready to forget that the past is never altogether annihilated, and that every step, however slight it may seem, which has once been taken in the movement of intellect, must be traversed again in order to understand the constitution of our pre sent intellectual world. To outward appearance the life and work of past generations have so completely lost their organic nature, with its unified and vital variety, that in their present phase they have turned into hard and opaque atoms of thought. The living forces of growth, as geologists tell us, which pulsed through the vegetables of one period are suspended and put in abeyance : and these vegetables turn into what we call the inorganic and inanimate strata of the earth. Similarly, when all vitality has been quenched or rendered torpid in the structures of thought, they sink into the material from which individuals draw their means of intellectual support. This inorganic material of thought stands to the mind, almost in the same way as the earth and its products stand to the body of a man. If the one is our material, the other is our spiritual substance. In the one our mind, as in the other our body, lives, moves, and has its being. XX.] THE SUBSTANCE OF HISTORICAL LIFE. 279 But in each case besides the practical need; which bids us consume the substance as dead matter, and apply it to use, there is the theoretical bent which seeks to reproduce ideally the past as a living and fully deve loped organism. 'This past/ says Hegel, ' is traversed by the individual, in the same way as one who begins to study a more advanced science repeats the preliminary lessons with which he had long been acquainted, in order to bring their information once more before his mind. He recalls them : but his interest and study are devoted to other things. In the same way the individual must go through all that is contained in the several stages in the growth of the universal mind : but all the while he feels that they are forms of which the mind has divested itself,— that they are steps on a road which has been long ago completed and levelled. Thus, points of learning, which in former times tasked the mature intellects of men, are now reduced to the level of exercises, lessons, and even games of boyhood : and in the progress of the schoolroom we may recognise the course of the education of the world, drawn, as it were, in shadowy outline1.' The scope of historical investigation therefore is this. It shows how every shading in the present world of thought, which makes our spiritual environment, has been once living and actual with an independent being of its own. But it also reveals the presence of shades and elements in the present which if our eyes had looked on the present alone we should scarcely have suspected : and it thus enables us to interpolate stages in development of which the result preserves only rudi mentary traces. And, when carried out in a philo sophical spirit, it shows further, that in those formations, which are produced in each period of the structural 1 Phenomenologie des Geistcs, p. 22. 28o PROLEGOMENA. [xx. development of reason, the universe of thought, or the Idea, is always whole and complete, but characterised in some special mode which for that period seems absolute and final. Each form or 'dimension' of thought, in which the totality is grasped and unified, is therefore not so simple or elementary as it may seem to casual observers regarding only the simplicity of language : it is a total, embracing more or less of simpler elements, each of which was once an inferior total, though in this larger sphere they are reduced to unity. Thus each term or period in the process is really an individualised whole, with a complex inter connexion and contrast included in it: it is concrete. No single word or phrase explains it : yet it is one totality,— a rounded life, from which its several spheres of life must be explained. But when that period is passing away, the form of its idea is separated, and re tained, apart frpm the life and mass of the elements which constituted it a real totality ; and then the mere shading or shell, with only part of its context of thought, is left abstract. When that time has come, a special form, a whole act in the drama, of humanity has been trans formed into an empty husk, and is only a name. The sensuous reality of life, as it is limited in space and time, and made palpable in matter and motion, is however the earliest cradle of humanity. The environ ment of sense is prior in the order of time to the environment of thought. Who, it may be asked, first wrought their way out of that atmosphere of sense into an ether of pure thought ? Who first saw that in sense there was yet present something more than sensation, — that the deliverances of sense-perception rest upon and involve relations, ties, distinctions, which contradict its self-confidence and carry us beyond its simple indi cations ? Who laid the first foundations of that world XX.] THE BEGINNINGS OF THOUGHT. 281 of reason in which the civilised nations of the modern period live and move ? The answer is, the Greek philosophers : and in the first place the philosophers of Elea. For Hegel the history of thought begins with Greece. All that preceded the beginnings of Greek speculation, and most that lies outside it, has only a secondary interest for the culture of the West. But 'many heroes lived before the days of Aga memnon/ The records of culture no longer begin with Greece. Even in Hegel's own day, voices, like those of the poet Riickert (in his 'habitation '-exercise), were heard declaring that the true fountain of European thought, the real philosophy, was to be sought in the remoter East. Since the time of Hegel, the study of primitive life, and of the rise of primitive ideas in morals and religion, has enabled us to some extent to trace the early gropings of barbarian fancy and reason. The comparative study of languages has, on the other hand, partly revealed the contrivances by which human reason has risen from one grade of consciousness to another. The sciences of language and of primitive culture have revealed new depths in the development of thought, where thought is still enveloped in nature and sense and symbols, — depths which were scarcely dreamed of in the earlier part of the present century. Here and there, investigators have even supposed that they had found the cradle of some elements in art, religion, and society, or, it may be, of humanity itself. These researches have accomplished much, and they promise to accomplish more. They help us perhaps to take a juster view of the early Greek thinkers, and show how much they still laboured under conditions of thought and speech from which their struggles have partly freed us. But for the present, and with certain 282 PROLEGOMENA. [xx explanations to be given later, it may still be said that the birthday of our modern world is the moment when the Greek sages began to construe the facts of the universe. Before their time the world lay, as it were, in a dream-life. Unconsciously in the womb of time the spirit of the world was growing, — its faculties forming in secresy and silence, — until the day of birth when the preparations were completed, and the young spirit drew its first breath in the air of thought. A new and to us all-important epoch in the history of thought begins with the Greeks : and the utterances of Parmenides mark the first hard, and still somewhat material, outlines of the spiritual world in which we live. Other nations of an older day had gathered the materials : in their languages, customs, religions, &c., there was an unconscious deposit of reason. It was reserved for the Greeks to recognise that reason : and thus in them reason became conscious. For us, then, it was the Greek philosophers who distinctly drew the distinction between sense and thought, and who first translated the actual forms of our natural life into their abbreviated equivalents in terms of logic. The struggle to carry through this transition, this elevation into pure thought, is what gives the dramatic interest to the Dialogues of Plato and keeps the sympathy of his readers always fresh. Socrates, we are told, first taught men to seek a general definition : not to be content with having — like Pytha goreans — their meaning wrapped up inseparably in psychical images and quasi-material symbols. He taught them to refer word to fellow word, to elicit the underlying idea by the collision and comparison of instances, to get at the 'content' which was identical in all the multiplicity of forms. He taught them, in brief, to think : and Plato carried out widely and deeply XX.] EARLY GREEK THOUGHT. 283 the lesson. The endeavour to create an ideal world, which, at its very creation, seems often to be trans formed into a refined and attenuated copy of the sense-world, meets us in almost every page of his Dialogues. In Aristotle this effort, with its concomitant tendency to give 'sensible* form to the ideal, is so far over and past; and some sort of intellectual world, perhaps narrow and inadequate, is reached,— the logical scheme in which immediate experience was expressed and codified. What these thinkers began, succeeding ages have inherited and promoted. In the environment of reason, therefore, which en compasses the consciousness of our age, are contained under a generalised form and with elimination of all the particular circumstances, the results won in the development of mind and morals. These results now constitute the familiar joints and supports in the frame work of ordinary thought: around and upon them cluster our beliefs and imaginations. During each epoch of history, the consciousness of the world, at first by the moutlj of its great men, its illustrious statesmen, artists, and philosophers, has explicitly re cognised, and translated into terms of thought,— into logical language,— that synthesis of the world which the period had practically secured by the action of its children. That activity went on, as is the way of natural activities, spontaneously, through the pressure of need, by an immanent adaptation of means to ends, not in conscious straining after a result. For the con scious or reflective effort of large bodies of men is often in a direction contrary to the Spirit of the Time. This Spirit of the Time, the absolute mind, which is neither religious nor irreligious, but infinite and absolute in its season, is the real motive principle of the world. But that Spirit of the Time is not always 284 PROLEGOMENA. [xx. the voice that is most effective at the poll, or rings loudest in public rhetoric. It is often a still small voice, which only the wise, the self-restrained, the unselfish hear. And he who hears it and obeys it, not he who follows the blatant crowd, is the hero. It is only to a mistaken or an exaggerated hero-worship, therefore, that Hegel can be said to be a foe. Great men are great : but the Spirit of the Time is greater : their greatness lies in understanding it and bringing it to consciousness. The man, who would act inde pendently of his time and in antagonism to it, is only the exponent of its latent tendencies. Nor need the syn thesis be always formulated by a philosopher in order to leaven the minds of the next generation. The whole system of thought,— the theory of the time,— its world, in short, influences minds, although it is not explicitly formulated and stated : it becomes the nursery of future thought and speculation. Philosophy in its articulate utterances only gives expression to the silent and half-conscious grasp of reason over its objects. But when the adaptation is not merely reached but seen and felt, when the synthesis or world of that time is made an object of self-consciousness, the ex position has made an advance upon the period which preceded. For that period started in its growth from the last exposition, the preceding system of philosophy, after it had become the common property of the age, and taken its place in their mental equipment. Each exposition or perception of the synthesis by the philosopher restores or re-affirms the unity which in the divided energies of the period, in its progressive, reforming, and reactionary aspects, in its differentia ting time, had to a great extent been lost. By the reforming, progressive, and scientific movement of which each period is full, the unity or totality with XX.] DIFFERENTIATION AND REDINTEGRATION. 285 which it began is shown to be defective. The value of the initial synthesis is impaired ; its formula is found inadequate to comprehend the totality : and the differ ences which that unity involved, or which were im plicitly in it, are now explicitly affirmed. But the bent towards unity is a natural law making itself felt even in the period of differentiation. And it makes itself felt in the pain of contradiction, of discord, of broken harmony. And that pain — which is the sign of an ever-present life that refuses to succumb to the encroaching elements — is the stimulus to re-construction. Only so far as pain ceases to be pain, as it benumbs, and deadens, does it involve stagnation : as pain proper, felt as resistance to an inner implicitly victorious principle, it stimulates and quickens to efforts to make life whole again. The integrating principle is present and active. There is then an effort, a re-action; the feeling has to do something to make itself outwardly felt: the implicit has to be actually put in its place, forced as it were into action and set forth * : and the existing contrasts and differences which the re-forming agency has called into vigorous life are lifted from their isolation and show of independence, and kept, as it were, suspended in the unity2. The differences are not lost or annihilated : but they come back to a centre, they find themselves, as it were, at home: they lose their unfair prominence and self-assertion, and sink into their places as constituents in the embracing or ganism 3. The unity which comes is not however the same as the unity which disappeared, however much it may seem so. The mere notion — the inner sense and inner unity — has put itself forward into the real world : it is no longer a mere subjective principle, but as moulded into actuality, into the objective world, 1 Gesetzt. 2 Aufgehoben. 3 Idee: Ideeller Weise. 286 PROLEGOMENA. [xx. it has become an Idea. (Begriff is now Idee.} For the Idea is always more than a notion : it is a notion translated into objectivity, and yet in objectivity not sinking into a mere congeries of independent parts, but retaining them 'ideally' — united by links of thought and service — in its larger ideal-reality. It is all that the object ought to be (and which in a sense it must be, if it is at all), and all that the subject sought to be and looked forward to. The mind of the world moves, as it were, in cycles, but with each new cycle a difference supervenes, a new tone is perceptible. History, which reflects the changing aspects of reality, does and does not repeat itself. The distinctions and the unity are neither of them the same after each step as they were before it : they have both suffered a change : it is a new scene that comes above the horizon, however like the last it may seem to the casual observer. Thus when the process of differentiation is repeated anew, it is repeated in higher terms, multiplied, and with a higher power or wider range of meaning1. Each unification however is a perfect world, a complete whole : it is the same sum of being ; but in each successive level of advance it receives a fuller expression, and a more complexly- grouped type of features 2. Such is the rhythmic movement, — the ebb and flow of the world, always recurring with the same burden but, as we cannot but hope, with richer variety of tones, and fuller sense of itself. The sum of actuality, the Absolute, is neither increased nor diminished. The world, the ultimate 1 Potenz. 2 ' Nicht nur die Einsicht in die Abhangigkeit des Einzelnen vom Ganzen ist allein das Wesentliche ; ebenso dass jedes Moment selbst unabhangig vom Ganzen das Ganze ist, und dies ist das Vertiefen in die Sache.' (Hegel's Leben, p. 548.) XX.] THE RHYTHM OF HISTORY. 287 reality of experience and life, was as much a rounded total to the Hebrew Patriarchs as it is to us : without advancing, it has been, we may say, in its expression deepened, developed, and organised. In one part of the sway of thought, however, there is a harder, narrower, insistance (by practical and business minds) on the sufficiency of a definite principle to satisfy all wants and to make all mysteries plain, and a disposition to ignore all other elements of life : at another, there is a fuller recognition of the differences, gaps, and con tradictions, involved in the last synthesis,— which recognition it is the tendency of scientific inquiry, of reforming efforts, of innovation, to produce: and in the last period of the sway, there is a stronger and more extended grasp taken by the unity pervading these differences,— which is the work appointed to philosophy gathering up the results of science and practical amendments. To this rhythmical movement Hegel has appropriated the name of pialectic^ The name came in the first instance from Kant, but ultimately from Plato, where it denotes the process which brings the ' many ' under the ' one/ and divides the 'one* into the 'many/ But how, it may be asked, does difference spring up, if we begin with unity, and how do the differences return into the unity? In other words, given a universal, how are we ever to get at particulars, and how will these particulars ever give rise to a real individual ? Such is the problem, in the technical language of the Logic of the ' Notion/ And we may answer, that the unity or universal in question is either a true and adequate or an imperfect unity. In the latter case it is a mere unit, amid other units, bound to them and serving to recall them by relations of contrast, complement, simi larity. It is one of many,— a subordinate member in 288 PROLEGOMENA. a congeries, and not the One. If, on the contrary, it be a true Unity, it is a concrete universal, — the parent of perpetual variety. The unity, if it be its genuine shape which is formulated by philosophers, is not mere monotony without differences. If it is a living and real Idea, containing a complex inter-action of prin ciples : it is not a single line of action, but the organic confluence of several. No one single principle by itself is enough to state a life, a character, or a period. But as the unity comes before the eye of the single thinker, it is seldom or never grasped with all its fulness of life and difference. The whole synthesis, although it is implicitly present and underlies experi ence and life as its essential basis, is not consciously apprehended, but for the most part taken on one side only, one emphatic aspect into which it has concentrated itself. And even if the master could grasp the whole, could see the unity of actuality in all its differences, (and we may doubt whether any man or any philoso pher can thus incarnate the prerogative of reason,) his followers and the popular mind would not imitate him. While his grasp of comprehension may possibly have been thorough, though he may have seen life whole through all its differences, inequalities, and schisms, and with all these reduced or idealised to their due proportions, into the unity beyond, the crowd who follow him are soon compelled to lay exclusive stress on some one side of his theory. Some of them see the totality from one aspect, some from another. It is indeed the whole which in a certain sense they see : but it is the whole narrowed down to a point. While his theory was a comprehensive and concrete grasp, including and harmonising many things which seem otherwise wide apart, theirs is abstract and inadequate : it fixes on a single point, which is thus withdrawn from XX.] THE RHYTHM OF HISTORY. 289 its living and meaning-giving context, and left as an empty name. Now it is the very nature of popular reasoning to tend to abstractions, in this sense of the word. Popular thought wants the time and persever ance necessary to retain a whole truth, and so is con tented with a partial image. It seeks for simple and sharp precision : it likes to have something distinctly before it, visible to the eye of imagination, and capable of being stated in a clear and unambiguous formula for the intellect. And popular thought — the dogmatic insistence on one-sided truth— is not confined to the so-called non-philosophic world : just as, on the other hand, the inclusive and comprehensive unity of life and reality is seen and felt and recognised by many— and felt by them first— who have no claim to the technical rank of philosophers. Popular thought is the thought which skims the surface of reality, which addresses itself to the level of opinion prevalent in all members of the mass as such, and does not go beyond that into the ultimate and complex depths of experience. Thus it comes about that the concrete or adequate synthesis which should have appeared in the self- conscious, thought of the period, when it reflected upon what it was, has been replaced by a narrow and one-sided formula, an abstract and formal universal, a universal which does not express all the particulars. One predominant side of the synthesis steals the place of the total : what should have been a comprehensive uni versal has lowered itself into a particular. Not indeed the same particular as existed before the union : because it has been influenced by the synthesis, so as to issue with a new colouring, as if it had been steeped in a fresh liquid. But still it is really a particular : and as such, it evokes a new particular in antagonism to it and ex hibiting an element latent in the synthesis. If the first 290 PROLEGOMENA. [xx. side of the antithesis which claims unduly to be the total, or universal, be called Conservative, the second must be called Reforming or Progressive. If the first step is Dogmatic, the second is Sceptical. If the one side assumes to be the whole, the other practically refutes the assumption. If the one agency clings blindly to the unity, — as when pious men rally round the central idea of religion, the other as tenaciously and narrowly holds to the difference, — as when science displays the struggle for existence and the empire of chance among the myriads of aimless organisms. They are two warring abstractions, each in a different direction. But as they are the offspring of one parent, — as they have each in their own way narrowed the whole down to a point, it cannot but be that when they evolve or develop all that is in them, they will ultimately coincide, and complete each other. The contradiction will not disappear until it has been persistently worked out, — when each opposing member which was potentially a total has become what it was by its own nature destined to be. And this disappear ance of the antithesis is the reappearance of the unity in all its strength, reinforced with all the wealth of new distinctions. Thus on a large scale we have seen the law of growth, of development, of life. It may be called growth by antagonism. But the antagonism here is over-ruled, and subject to the guidance of an indwelling unity. Mere antagonism — if there be such a thing- would lead to nothing. A mere positive or affirmative point of being would lead to no antithesis, were it not, so to speak, a point floating in an ether of larger life and being, whence it draws an outside element which it overcomes, assimilates and absorbs. A bare national mind only grows to richer culture, because it lives in XX.] PROGRESS BY ANTAGONISM. 291 a universal human life, and can say Nihil humani a me alienum puto. So too the mere unit is always tainted with a dependence on outside : or it is always implicitly more than a mere unit : and what seems to come upon it from outside, is really an enemy from within, and it falls because there is treason within its walls. The revolution succeeds because the party of conservative order is not so hard and homogeneous as it appears. So, too, it is the immanent presence of the complete thought, of the Idea, which is the heart and moving spring that sets going the pulse of the universal move ment of thought, and which reappears in every one of these categories to which the actualised thought of an age has been reduced. In every term of thought there are three stages or elements : the original narrow definiteness, claiming to be self-sufficient, — the antagon ism and criticism to which this gives rise, — and the union which results when the two supplement and modify each other. In the full life and organic unity of every notion there is a definite kernel, with rigid outlines as if it were immovable : there is a revulsion against such exclusiveness, a questioning and critical attitude : and there is the complete notion, where the two first stages interpenetrate. U 2 CHAPTER XXI. ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE I AND THE ORDINARY LOGIC. THE ordinary logic-books have made us all familiar with the popular distinction between Abstract and Concrete. By a concrete term they mean the name of an existence or reality which is obvious to the senses, and is found in time and place ; — or they mean the name of an attribute when we expressly or tacitly recognise its dependence upon such a thing of the senses. When, on the contrary, the attribute is forcibly withdrawn from its context and made an independent entity in the mind, the term expressing it becomes in the usual phraseology abstract. Any term therefore which denotes a non-sensible or intelligible object would probably be called abstract. And there is some thing to be said for the distinction, which, though unsuccessful in its expression, has some feeling of the radical antithesis between mere being and mere thought. It is true, that in the totality of sense and feeling, in the full sense-experience, there is a concrete fulness, as it were, an infinite store of features and phases waiting for subsequent analysis to detect. In the real kind of actual nature there is an inexhaustible mine of properties, which no artificial classification and description can ever come to the end of. Every quality ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE. 293 which we state, every relation which we predicate, is a partial and incomplete element in this presupposed reality, this implicit concrete ; and as such is abstract, and comparatively unreal. It is something forcibly torn out of and held apart from its context. But on the other hand the concrete reality is not at first real, but implicit : it becomes really concrete only as it re- embraces, and re-constitutes in its totality the elements detected by analysis. But the popular distinction forgets this, and gives the title and rank of concrete to what very poorly deserves the name, viz. to the yet undiscerned reality denoted by a substantive name. Yet there can be little doubt that the popular use of these terms, or the^ popular apprehension of what constitutes reality,— for that is what it comes to,— is sufficiently represented by the ordinary logic-books. So that, if the whole business of the logician lies in formulating the distinctions prevalent in popular thought, the ordinary logic is correct. Now the popular logic of the day,— the logic which has long been taught in our schools and universities has three sources.— In the first place, but in a slight degree, it trenches upon the province of psychology, and gives some account of the operation by which concepts or general ideas are supposed to be formed, and of the errors or fallacies which naturally creep into the process of reasoning. This is the more strictly modern, the descriptive part of our logic-books.— But, secondly, the logic of our youth rests in a much higher degree upon the venerable authority of Aristotle. That logic, within its own compass, was a masterpiece of analysis, and for many centuries maintained an ascen dency over the minds of men, which it well deserved. But it was not an analysis of thought or knowledge as a whole, and it treated its subject in fragments. It 294 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. gave in one place an analysis of science and in another an analysis of certain methods, which could be observed in popular discussions and practical oratory. As Lord Bacon remarked, it did little else than state and, it may be, exaggerate the rationale of argumentation. A high level of popular thought it unquestionably was, which Aristotle had to investigate, — a level which many generations of less favoured races were unable to reach. But there were defects in this Logic which fatally marred its general usefulness, when the limited scope of its original intention had been lost sight of. The thoughts of Greece, it has been said, were greatest and most active in the line of popular action for the city and the public interest, in the discussions, the quibbles, the fallacies, and rhetorical arts of the barber's shop and the 'agora/ The aim of such exercises was to convince, to demonstrate, to persuade, to overcome ; — it might be for good and truth, but also it might not. And accordingly the Logic of Aristotle has been said to have for its end and canon the power to convince and to give demonstrative certainty. There is some ground, it may be, for this charge. The ancient logician seems to luxuriate in a rank growth of forms of sophism, and in an almost childlike fondness for variety of argumentative method. He seems resolved to trace the wayward tricks of thought and its phases through every nook and cranny, to exhaust all the permutations and complications of its elements. But let us be just, and remember that all this was in the main a specula tive inquiry — for the sake of theory. It developed the powers of judgment and inference, just as the modern research for new metals, new plants, or new planets, develops the powers of observation. Both have some value in the material results they discover : but, after all, the mental culture they give is the main thing. And xxi.] ARISTOTLE'S LOGIC. 295 the talents quickened by deductive research are no whit less valuable than those owed to the other. Forms are essential, even if it be possible to make the terrible mistake of regarding them as all-important to the ex clusion of matter. And then, this is not the whole truth. There is a per fectly serious Greek science— Mathematics— a science of many branches : a science which, from Plato down wards, always stood in alliance with the studies of philosophy. Now, it might be said, perhaps with ground, that the conception of mathematical method too much dominated all attempts to get at the rationale of science, and led to the supremacy of syllogism. It would be fairer perhaps to put this objection in another shape. We should then say that the logic of Aristotle, —the Analytics— is too much restricted to dealing with the most general and elementary principles of reasoning. But this is not in itself a fault. It becomes a fault only where there is no growth in philosophy — when it is merely handed on from master to pupil ; and where there is a tendency to put philosophic doctrine to immediate use. To expend the whole energy of intellect in laying bare the general principles, the fundamental method, of knowledge and inference, is precisely what the founder of a science has a duty to do. But the beginning thus made requires development —and development which is fruitful must proceed by cor rection and antithesis, no less than by positive additions. It was not given to Aristotle's logic to be so carried on. His logic, like his system in general, had no real suc cessor to carry it on in the following generation : and when in the less original ages of early Byzantine rule it again found students, it had become a quasi-sacred text which could only be commented on, not modified and developed. From the great Exegetai of Greece it 296 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. passed westward to Boethius and eastward to the Syrian and Persian commentators in the early centuries of the Caliphate. From these, and from other inter mediaries, it may be, it finally culminated in the work of the Latin Schoolmen of the later Middle Ages. But the very reverence which all these expositors felt for the text of the Philosopher rendered true development impossible. Then; on the other hand, the lust of practical utility caused a grave misconception of what logic can do. For Aristotle, logic is a scientific analysis of the modes of inference ; its uses are those which follow intrinsi cally from all noble activity freely and zealously prose cuted. But with the death of Aristotle the great days of knowledge for the sake of knowledge and divine wisdom were over. The Stoics into whose hands the chief sceptre of philosophy, directly or indirectly, passed never rose above the conception of life as a task and a duty, and of all other things, literature, science, and art, as subservient to the performance of that task. The conception is an ennobling one : but only with a relative or comparative nobility. It ennobles, if it is set beside and against the view that life is a frivolous play, a sport of caprice and selfishness. But it darkens and narrows the outlook of humanity, when it loses sight of life as a j°y> a self-enlarging and self-realising freedom, of life as in its supreme phase e^copta — or the enjoyment of God. To the Stoic, therefore, — and to the dominant Christian theory which entered to some extent on the Stoic inheritance — logic, like the rest of philosophy, was something only valuable because ultimately it helped to save the soul. It thus sunk into the position of an Organon or instru ment. To the Stoic, — for instance to Epictetus— its value was its use to establish the doctrines of the Stoic XXI.] ARISTOTL&S LOGIC. 297 faith, by confuting the ill-arranged and futile inferences on which were founded the aims and approvals of ordinary worldly life. To the Christian, again, it served as a method for putting into systematic shape (under the guidance of certain supreme categories or principles also borrowed from Greek thought) the variety of fundamental and derivative aspects which suc cessive minds, pondering on the power and mystery of the Christian faith, had set forward as its essential dogmas. It thus helped to build up (out of the leading ideas of Greek metaphysics, and the principles emerging in the earliest attempts to formulate the law of Christ) that amalgam of the power of a divine life with the reflective thought of the teachers of successive genera tions, which constitutes the dogmatic creed of Christen dom. Such a reconstruction in thought of the reality which underlies experience — (in this case the experi ence of the Christian life), is inevitable if man is to be man, a free intelligence, and not a mere animal-like feeling. But its success is largely, if not entirely, dependent on the value of the logic and metaphysics which it employs : and it would be a bold thing to say that the subtle, abstract, and unreal system of Neo- Platonist and Nee-Aristotelian thought was an organon adequate to cope with the breadth and depth, latent if not very explicit, in the fulness and reality of the religious life. Yet even as an Organon, Logic had to sink to a lower rank. As traditionalism grew supreme, and religion ossified into a stereotyped form of belief and practice, logic had less to do as an organiser of dogma. It sank, or seemed to sink (for it would be rash to speak too categorically of an epoch of thought so far removed from modern sympathy and understanding as the age of the Schoolmen), into a futile (and as it seems 298 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. occasionally almost a viciously-despairing) play with pro and contra, — into a lust of argumentation which in masters like Ockam comes perilously close to scepticism or agnosticism. More and more, Scholastic thought, which, at one time, had been in the centre of such intellectual life as there was, came to be stranded on the shore, while the onward-flowing tide spread in other directions. These were the great days of logical sway, when it seemed as if logic could create new truth : as if forms could beget matter. So at least ran an outside rumour, which was probably based on some amount of real folly. But the more important point was that the old logic had lost touch with reality. New problems were arising, which it was — without a profound reconstruction — quite incapable of solving. Of these there were obviously two — not unconnected perhaps, but arising in different spheres of life. There was the revival of religious experience, growing especi ally since the thirteenth century with an ever-swelling stream in the souls of men and women, till it burst through all bounds of outward organisation in the catastrophe of the Reformation. Luther may have been historically unjust (as Bacon afterwards was) to the 'blind heathen master/ as he called Aristotle : but he was governed by a true instinct when (unlike the com promise-loving Melanchthon) he found the traditional system of logic and metaphysics no proper organon for the new phase of faith and theory. So, too, the new attempts at an inception and instauration of the sciences grew up outside the walls of old tradition, and were at first perhaps discouraged and persecuted as infidel and heretical, and were, even without that burden, pursued at much hap-hazard and with much ignorance both in aims and methods. Intelligent onlookers, — especially if inspired by an enthusiasm for the signs of an age XXL] MODERN LOGIC. 299 happier for human welfare — could not but see how needful it was to come to some understanding on the aims and methods of the rising sciences. This want, which he keenly felt, Francis Bacon tried to satisfy. He pointed out, vaguely, but zealously and in a noble spirit, the end which that new logic had to accomplish. Bacon, however, could not do more than state these bold suggestions : he had not the power to execute them. He imagined indeed that he could display a method, by which science would make incredible advances, and the kingdom of truth in a few years come into the world. But this is a sort of thing which no man can do. Plato, if we take his Republic for a political pamphlet, had tried to do it for the social life of Athens. What Plato could not do for the political world of Greece, Bacon could not do for the intellectual world in his time : for as the Athenian worked under the shadow of his own state, over-mastered even without his knowledge by the ordinances of Athens, so the Englishman was evidently enthralled by the medieval conceptions and by the logic which he condemned. What Aristotle had for ages been supposed to do, no philosopher could do for the new spirit of inquiry which had risen in and before the days of Bacon. That spirit, as exhibited in his great contemporaries, Bacon, as he has himself shown, could not rightly understand or appreciate. He failed, above all, to recognise the self-corrective, tenta tive, and hypothetical nature, of all open inquiry. But one need not for this disparage his work. It showed a new sense of the magnitude of the modern problem : it set prominently forward the comprehensive aim of human welfare : and by its conception of the ' forma * it kept science pledged to a high ideal. But Bacon could only play the part of the guide-post : he could not 300 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. himself lay down the road. And negatively he could warn against the belief that mathematics could generate or do more indeed than define the sciences. The spirit of free science, of critical investigation, of inductive inquiry, must and did constitute its forms, legislation, and methods for itself. For no philosopher can lay down laws or methods beforehand which the sciences must follow. The logician only comes after, and, appreciating and discovering the not always con spicuous methods of knowledge, endeavours to gather them up and give them their proper place in the grand total of human thought, correcting its inadequacies by their aid, and completing their divisions by its larger unities. Or rather this is a picture of what English logic might have done. But it does not do so in the ordinary and accepted text-books on the subject. What it does do, is rather as follows. To the second and fundamental part which it subjects to a few unimportant alterations, — i. e. to the doctrine of terms, propositions, and reasonings, — it subjoins an enumeration of the methods used in the sciences. To the rude minds of the Teutonic peoples the logical system of Aristotle had seemed almost a divine revelation. From the brilliant intellect of Greece a hand was stretched to help them in the arrangement of their religious beliefs. The Church accepted the aid of logic, foreign though logic was to its natural bent, as eagerly as the young society tried for a while to draw support from the ancient forms of the Roman Empire. So with the advance of the Sciences in modern times some hopeful spirits looked upon the Inductive Logic of Mill in the light of a new revelation. The vigorous action of the sciences hailed a systematic account of its methods almost as eagerly as the strong, but untaught intellect of the barbarian world welcomed XXI.] MODERN LOGIC. 301 the lessons of ancient philosophy. For the first time the sciences, which had been working blindly or in stinctively, but with excellent success, found their procedure stated clearly and definitely, yet without any attempt to reduce their varied life to the Procrustean bed of mathematics, which had once been held to possess a monopoly of method. The enormous influ ence of the physical sciences saw itself reflected in a distinct logical outline: and the new logic became the dominant philosophy. Such for a while was the proud position of the Inductive Logic. Enthusiastic students of science in all countries, who were not inaccessible to wider culture, used quotations from Mill to adorn and authorise their attempts at generalisation and theory. A period of speculation in the scientific world succeeded the period .of experiment, in which facts had been collected and registered. A chapter on Method became a necessary introduction to all higher scientific treatises. In our universities methodology was prodigally applied to the study of ancient philo sophy. And so long as the scientific epoch lasts in its one-sided prominence, so long the theory of inductive and experimental methods may dominate the intellec tual world. But the Inductive Logic hardly rose to the due sense of its situation. It has not held to the same high ideal as Bacon set before it. It has planted itself beside what it was good enough to call the Deductive Logic, and given the latter a certain toleration as a harmless lunatic, or an old pauper who had seen better days. Retaining the latter with certain modifications, although it has now lost its meaning in the changed outlines of the intellectual world, Inductive Logic adds a method ology of the sciences, without however founding this methodology upon a comprehensive analysis of know- 302 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. ledge as a whole, when enlarged and enlightened by the work of the sciences. Hence the two portions,— the old logic, mutilated and severed from the Greek world it grew out of, and the new Inductive or specially- scientific logic, not g6ing beyond a mere classification of methods, — can never combine, any more than oil and water. And the little psychology, which is some times added, does not facilitate the harmony. But Inductive Logic should have adopted a more thorough policy. There can only be one Logic, which must be both inductive and deductive, but exclusively, and in parts, neither. To achieve that task however Logic must not turn its back indifferently on what it calls metaphysics, and it must rise to a higher con ception of the problems of what it calls psychology. In these circumstances the ordinary logic, in its fundamental terms, is more on the level of popular thought, than in a strictly scientific region, and does not attempt to unite the two regions, and examine the fundamental basis of thought on which scientific methods rest. The case of Concrete and Abstract will illustrate what has been said. To popular thought the sense- world is concrete : the intellectual world abstract. And so it is in the ordinary logic. To Hegel, on the con trary, the intellectual interpretation of the world of reality and experience is a truer and thus a more concrete description of it than that contained in a series of sense-terms. Now the difference between the two uses of the term is not a mere arbitrary change of names. When the philosopher denies the concreteness of the sense-world, and declares that it, as merely sen sible, is only a mass of excluding elements, a 'manifold/ and in the second instance a series of abstractions, drawn out of this congeries by perception, the change of language marks the total change of position between xxi.] ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE. 303 the philosophic and the popular consciousness. Reality and concreteness as estimated by the one line of thought are the very reverse of those of the other. A mere sense-world to the philosopher is a world which wants unity, which is made up of bits imperfectly adjusted to each other, and always leading us to look for an ex planation of them in sources outside them. The single things we say we perceive,— the here and the now we perceive them in— are found, upon reflection and analysis, to depend upon general laws, on relations that go beyond the single,— on what is neither here nor now, but everywhere and timeless. The reality of the thing is found to imply a general system of relations which make it what it is. Sense-perception in short is the beginning of knowledge : and it begins by taking up its task piecemeal. It rests upon a felt totality : and to raise this to an intelligible totality, it must at first only isolate one attribute at a time. The apprehension of a thing from one side or aspect, —the apprehension of one thing apart from its con nexions,— the retention of a term or formula apart from its context, — is what Hegel terms 'abstract/ Ordinary terms are essentially abstract. They spring from the analysis of something which would, in the first stage of the process, in strictness be described not as concrete, but as chaos :— as the indefinite or 'manifold' of sensation. But the first conceptions, which spring from this group when it is analysed, are abstract : they are each severed from the continuity of their reality. To interpret our feeling, our experience as felt, we must break it up. But the first face that presents itself is apt to impress us unduly, and seems more real, because nearer feeling : on the other it is more unreal, because less adequate as a total expression of the felt unity. In the same sense we call Political Economy 304 PROLEGOMENA. [xxi. an abstract science, because it looks upon man as a money-making and money-distributing creature, and keeps out of sight his other qualities. Our notions in this way are more abstract or more concrete, according as our grasp of thought extends to less or more of the relations which are necessarily pre-supposed by them. On the other hand, when a term of thought owns and emphasises its solidarity with others, when it is not circumscribed to a single relation, but becomes a focus in which a variety of relations converge, when it is placed in its right post in the organism of thought, its limits and qualifications as it were recognised and its degree ascertained, — then that thought is rendered ' con crete.' A concrete notion is a notion in its totality, looking before and after, connected indissolubly with others : a unity of elements, a meeting-point of opposites. An abstract notion is one withdrawn from everything that naturally goes along with it, and enters into its constitution. All this is no disparagement of abstrac tion. To abstract is a necessary stage in the process of knowledge. But it is equally necessary to insist on the danger of clinging, as to an ultimate truth, to the pseudo-simplicity of abstraction, which forgets alto gether what it is in certain situations desirable for a time to overlook. In a short essay, with much grim humour and quaint illustrations, Hegel tried to show what was meant by the name ' abstract/ which in his use of it denotes the cardinal vice of the ' practical ' habit of mind. From this essay, entitled ' Who is the Abstract Thinker l ? ' it may be interesting to quote a few lines. 'A murderer is, we may suppose, led to the scaffold. In the eyes of the multitude he is a murderer and nothing more. The ladies perhaps may make the remark that he is 1 ' Wer denkt abstrakt?' (l^ermischte Schriften, vol. ii. p. 402.) XXL] ABSTRACT AND CONCRETE, 305 a strong, handsome, and interesting man. At such a remark the populace is horrified. " What ! a murderer handsome ? Can anybody's mind be so low as to call a murderer handsome? You must be little better your selves." And perhaps a priest who sees into the heart, and knows the reasons of things, will point to this remark, as evidence of the corruption of morals pre vailing among the upper classes. A student of character, again, inquires into the antecedents of the criminal's up-bringing : he finds that he owes his existence to ill- assorted parents ; or he discovers that this man has suffered severely for some trifling offence, and that under the bitter feelings thus produced he has spurned the rules of society, and cannot support himself other wise than by crime. No doubt there will be people who when they hear this explanation will say " Does this person then mean to excuse the murderer ? " In my youth I remember hearing a city magistrate com plain that book-writers were going too far, and trying to root out Christianity and good morals altogether. Some one, it appeared, had written a defence of suicide. It was horrible ! too horrible ! On further inquiry it turned out that the book in question was the Sorrows of Werther. 'By abstract thinking, then, is meant that in the murderer we see nothing but the simple fact that he is a murderer, and by this single quality annihilate all the human nature which is in him. The polished and sentimental world of Leipsic thought otherwise. They threw their bouquets, and twined their flowers round the wheel and the criminal who was fastened to it. — But this also is the opposite pole of abstraction. — It was in a different strain that I once heard a poor old woman, an inmate of the workhouse, rise above the abstraction of the murderer. The sun shone, as the x 3o6 PROLEGOMENA. severed head was laid upon the scaffold. " How finely," said the woman, " does God's gracious sun lighten up Binder's head ! " We often say of a poor creature who excites our anger that he is not worth the sun shining on him. That woman saw that the murderer's head was in the sunlight, and that it had not become quite worthless. She raised him from the punishment of the scaffold into the sunlit grace of God. It was not by wreaths of violets or by sentimental fancies that she brought about the reconciliation : she saw him in the sun above received into grace.' CHAPTER XXII. FROM SENSE TO THOUGHT. INDUCTION and Experience are names to which is often assigned the honour of being the source of all our knowledge. But what induction and experience consist in, is what we are supposed to be already aware of; and that is— it may be briefly said— the concentration of the felt and sense-given fragments into an intimate unity. The accidents and fortunes that have befallen us in lapses of time, the scenes that have been set before and around us in breadths of space, are condensed into a mood of mind, a habitual shading of judgment, or frame of thought. The details of fact re-arrange themselves into a general concept ; their essence gets distilled into a concentrated form. Their meaning disengages itself from its embodiment, and floats as a self-sustaining form in an ideal world. Thus if we look at the larger process of history, we see every period trying to translate the sensuous fact of its life into a formula of thought, and to fix it in definite characters. The various parts of existence, and exist ence as a whole, are stripped of their sensible or factual nature, in which we originally feel and come into contact with them, and are reduced to their simple equivalents in terms of thought. From sense and immediate feeling there is, in the first place, generated an image or idea which at least represents and stands for reality ; and from that, in the second place, comes X 2 308 PROLEGOMENA. [xxn. a thought or notion proper, which holds the facts in unity. The phenomenon may, perhaps, be illustrated by the case of numbers. To the adult European, numbers and numbering are an obvious and essential part of our scheme of things that seems to need no special ex planation. But the experience of children suggests its artificiality, and the evidence from the history of language corroborates that surmise. If number be in a way describable as part of the sense-experience, or total impression, it certainly does not come upon us with the same passivity on our part as the perception of taste or colour, or even of shape. It postulates a higher grade of activity. As Plato says, it ' awakes the intelli gence ' : it implies a question and looks forward to an answer : it is thus the first appearance of what in its later fullness will be called ' Dialectic/ To put it otherwise : Numbering can only proceed where there is a unit, and an identity : it implies a one, and it implies an infinite repetibility of that one \ It thus postulates the double mental act, first of reducing the various to its basis of identity, and, secondly, of performing a synthesis of the identical units thus created. In the highly artificial world in which we live all this seems simple enough. The products of machinery, articles of furniture, dress, &c., &c., are already uniform items : and the strokes of a clock seem almost to invite summation. But in free nature this similarity is much less obviously stamped on things : and the products of primitive art — of literal manu-facture — display an individuality, an element of personal taste, even, which is necessarily lacking in things turned out by machinery. Thus it was necessary, before we could number, to reduce the qualitatively different to a quantitative equality or com- 1 See vol. ii. p. 190, (Logic, § 102). XXI1-] NUMBER. 309 parability. There are indeed some instances, in that nearest of things to us, the human body, which might help. There is the obvious similarity of organs and limbs which go in pairs, and which might easily suggest a dual, as, so to speak, a sensuous fact amongst other facts. Again, there is the hand and its five fingers, or the two hands and the ten fingers. The five or ten, as a whole naturally given, suggest a grouping of numbers in natural aggregates. The fingers, again, (and here we may keep at first to the fingers proper, minus the thumb,) may be without much ingenuity said to give us a set of four, naturally distinct, yet naturally alike, and needing, so to speak, the minimum of intelligence to create the numerical scale from one to four. It is by them, indeed, that Plato, it may be unconsciously, illustrates the genesis of number. Here in short you have the natural abacus of the nations, but one re stricted, first, perhaps to the group 1-4, secondly to the group i-io. We have seen how the dual was, in certain instances, almost a natural perceptive fact. But when it is so envisaged, it is hardly recognised as number strictly so called. It is only a fresh and peculiar sensuous at tribute of things : a thing which has the quality of duplication, not a thought which is the synthesis of two identical units. It is a sort of accident, not part of a regular system or series. So again with the plural, which may appear in several shapes before it is as signed to its proper place as a systematic function of the singular. If the Malay, in order to say 'the king of all apes ' has to enumerate one after another the several sub-species of ape, or if to express 'houses' he has to reduplicate the singular, to insert a word mean ing 'all ' or 'many,' we can see that the conception of number is for him still in the bonds of sense. It is not 310 PROLEGOMENA. [xxil. a synthetic category, but only a material multitude. But in other cases the plural proper is almost con founded with the so-called ' collective/ It is not an unfamiliar fact in Greek and Latin that the plural has acquired a meaning of its own, — not the mere multiple of its singular; as also that the collective term is occasionally used as an abstract, occasionally as the more or less indeterminate collection of the individuals. Such plurals and such collectives represent a stage of language and conception when the aggregate of singu lars form a uniquely-qualified case of the object. And the peculiarity of them is seen in the way the plurality is immersed in and restricted to the special class of objects : as e. g. when in English the plurality of a number of ships is verbally stereotyped as against the plurality of a number of sheep, or of partridges (fleet, flock, covey). In such instances the category of number is completely pervaded and modified by the quality of the objects it is applied to. So, in the Semitic languages, the so-called ' broken plural ' is a quasi-collective, which grammatically counts as a feminine singular (like so many Latin and Greek collectives) : and whereas the more regular plural is generally shown by separable affix, this quasi-collective plural enters the very body of the word by vowel- change, indicating as it were by this absorption the constitution of a specifically new view of things. On the other hand, it may be said, there is in this collective a trace of the emergence of the universal and identical element through the generalisation due to the con junction of several similars all acting as one l. In a true plural, on the contrary, it is required that the sign of number be clearly eliminated from any peculiari ties of its special object, and be distinctly separated 1 See Max Miiller in Mind, vol. i. 345. XXII.] DUAL AND PLURAL. 311 from the collective. And similarly the true numeral has to be realised in its abstractness, as a category per se. And to do this requires some amount of abstraction. In Greek, for example, we meet the dis tinction between numbers in the abstract, pure numbers (such as four and six), and bodily or physical numbers (such as four men, six trees) \ The geometrical aspect under which numbers were regarded by the Greeks, e. g. as oblong or square numbers, bears in the same direction. But another phenomenon in language tells the tale more distinctly 2. Abundantly in Sanscrit and Greek, more rarely in Zend and Teutonic, and here and there in the Semitic languages, we meet with what is known as the dual number, a special grammatical form intended to express a pair of objects. The witty remark of Du Ponceau 3 concerning the Greek dual, that it had apparently been invented only for lovers and married people, may illustrate its uses, but hardly suffices to explain its existence in language. But a comparison of barbarian dialects serves to show that the dual is, as it were, a prelude to the plural, — a first attempt to grasp the notion of plurality in a definite way, which served its turn in primitive society, but afterwards disappeared, when the plural had been developed, and the numerals had attained a form of 1 Pure number is apiOpos ftovaSitcos : applied number is apiOfios £a, — the level of consciousness which fails to rise to see the unity of essence in the many single goods and beauties, which holds its knowledge (such at is) at the mercy of acci dents, not bound by the conclusions of reasoning, — the realm which is not without reality, but an immature and uncertain reality. It is, in essentials, the same as what, as opposed to intellectus, Spinoza styled imaginatio. xxiii.] PICTURE-THINKING. 329 Imagination, to Spinoza, is an understanding under the bondage of particular passions and temporary interests, which loses sight of the great bond of being or Substantia, and fixes its glance on the parts in subordinate and infra-essential relationships : which is always finite, i. e. never really comprehensive and self-sustaining in its view, but always limited by a tacit reference to some thing outside itself. The ' Representation ' is the idea, in the loose and inexact use of that word, which goes with the phrase mere idea, — i. e. a mere mental image, which is not the reality, though it is believed to do duty for and to represent it *. Yet it is not a mere thought : rather its whole aim and meaning is to refer to reality, to suggest it, to bring it nearer us. Its fault is that it is an imperfect, partial, one-sided, or even one-pointed idea. It is really an instance and phase of the ignava ratio, to which a date or name serves as a TTOU o-rco of explanation. 'At Kilne there was no weathercock, And that 's the reason why.' Such ' representation/ according to Hegel, is, e. g., the mode of intelligence accessible to those who cling to the mere, or abstractly, religious mood, and who cannot or will not rise to the comprehension of their creed. Its facts or dogmas present themselves to such a restricted conception as the parts of a picture or the stages of a history, in visible or imaginatively-constru- able space, and in a succession of times. The essence of religion, of course, for Hegel as for other exponents of its inmost nature, is a feeling of certitude or faith which transcends the gulfs and separations of the secular consciousness, which sees with the believing soul the 1 Hegel's Werke, ii. 431 : ' Wobei das Selbst nur reprasentirt und vorgestellt 1st, da ist es nicht wirklich : wo es vertreten 1st, ist es nicht.' Cf. ib. 416. 330 PROLEGOMENA. [xxill. inner peace, the absolute harmony of the true reality. Pectusfacit theologum. The sense of utter dependence on God, incomplete identity with the sense of absolute independence in God— that strength of faith is the very life of religion. But when religion seeks to give an intelligent expression of her faith, when she tries to give a reason acceptable to the outside world, she is apt, unless specially trained in the high things of the spirit, to base her creed not on the rock of ages, but on the signs and miracles of the times. She has tried to theorise the faith : but, although her faith may be sound and true, the religious spirit, unless it be also the spirit of wisdom and reasoned truth, runs a risk of falling into the fallacy of Post hoc, ergo propter hoc. She descends therefore to the region of representation : she uses the language of sense and analogy ; she presents the spiri tual under the guise of the natural. Yet in her heart of hearts these things are only a parable, — they are but ' Flesh and blood To which she links a truth divine.' Hegel— in the introduction to his lectures on the Philo sophy of Religion— is reported to have given the follow ing characteristics of 'representation/ (a) It is still trammeled by the senses. Thought and sensation strive for the mastery in it. Thought is bound fast to an illustration : and of this illustration it cannot as representative thought divest itself:— the eternally living idea is chained to the transient and perishable form of sense. It is metaphorical and material thinking, which is helpless without the metaphor and the matter. (b) Representative thought envisages what is timeless and infinite under the conditions of time and space. It loses sight of the moral and spirit of historical develop ment under the semblance of the names, incidents, and forms in which it is displayed. The historical and philo- xxill.] PICTURE- THINKING. 3 3 1 sophical sense is lost under the antiquarian. Repre sentative thought keeps the shell, and throws away the kernel, (c) The terms by which such a materialised thought describes its objects are not internally con nected : each is independent of the other ; and we only bring them together for the occasion by an act of subjec tive arrangement1. The thing — the so-called subject of the properties, of which it is really no more than the substratum — affords no sufficient ground for the unity of the properties attached to it. The substratum or subject of the propo sition is given, and we then look around to see what other properties accompany the primary characteristic for which the name was applied. But the term of popular language is not a real unity capable of support ing differences ; it is only one aspect of a thing, a single point fixed and isolated in the process of language by the action of natural selection. And so, to ask how the properties are related to the thing, is to ask how one aspect, taken out of its setting, is related to another isolated aspect : which is evidently an unanswerable question. Science is right in rejecting the 'thing* of popular conception. If a is a, and nothing more, as the law of Identity informs us, then it is for ever impossible to get on to b, c, d, and the rest. The union between the thing divided or defined, and its divided or defining members, is what is termed extra-logical ; in other words, it is not evident from what is given or stated in the popular conception. That union must be sought elsewhere, and deeper. And when we step in to overcome the repugnance which the point of conception, or what is supposed the subject, shows against admitting a diversity of predicates, —when we force it into union with these properties : or 1 Philosophic der Religion, i. p. 137 seqq. 332 PROLEGOMENA. [xxm. when we try to remove the separation which leaves the cause and effect as two independent things to fall apart ; our action, by which we effect a unification of differences, may, from another and a universal point of view, be said to be the notion, or grasp of thought, coming to the consciousness of itself. Thought, as it were, recognises itself and its image in those objects of representative conception, which seem to be given and imposed upon the intellect. The two worlds, which the understanding accepts as each solid and independent,— the world of external objects or conceptions, and the world of self, — meet and coincide in the free agency of thought, developing itself under a double aspect. It is the 'original synthetical unity of apperception ' (to quote Kant's words), from which the Ego or thinking subject, and the 'manifold' or body and world, are simultaneously differentiated. Thus, on the one hand, we ourselves no longer remain a rigid unity, existing in antithesis to the objects presupposed or referred to by representative thought : and on the other hand the so-called thing loses its hardness and fragmentary independence, as distinguished from our apprehension of it. Our action, as we incline to call it, which mends the inadequacies of terms, is from a philosophic point of view, the notion itself coming to the front and claiming recognition. The process of thought is then seen to be a totality, of which our faculties, on the one hand, and the existing thing, on the other, are isolated abstractions, supposed habitually to exist on their own account. To view either of these systems, the mental, on the one hand, and the objective world, on the other, as self-subsistent, has been the error in much of our metaphysics, and in the popular conceptions of what constitutes reality. The idealism of metaphysicians has been often as narrow and insufficient as the realism of common sense. An XXIII.] REPRESENTATION AND THOUGHT. 333 adequate philosophy, on the contrary, recognises the presence of both elements, in a subordinate and forma tive position. Representations may be compared to the little pools left here and there by the sea amongst the rocks and sand : the notion, or grasp of thought, is the tidal wave, which left them there to stagnate, but comes back again to restore their continuity with the great sea. In our thinking we are only the ministers and inter preters of the Idea, — of the organic and self-developing system of thought. The difference between a representative conception and a thought proper may be illustrated by the case of the term ' Money/ Money may be either a materialised thought, i. e. a Representative Conception, or a Notion Proper. In the former case, money is identified with a piece of money. It is probably, in the first instance, embodied in coins of gold, silver, and bronze. In the second place, a wide gulf is placed between it and the other articles for which it is given in exchange. If other things are regarded as money, they are generally treated on the assumption that they can in case of need be reduced to coinage. The conception of money by the unscientific vulgar considers it separately from other commodities : and the laws which forbade its exportation gave a vigorous expression to the belief that it was something sui generis, and subject to con ditions of its own. The scientific notion of money modifies this belief in the peculiarity and fixity of money. Science does so historically, when it can point to a time and a race where money in our sense of the word does not exist, and where barter takes the place of buying and selling. Science does so philosophically, when it expounds what may be called the process of money, — the inter-action or meeting of conditions to which the existence of money is due. The notion of 334 PROLEGOMENA. money, as given in the Ethics of Aristotle, says that it is the common measure of utility or demand. When we leave out of sight the specific quality of an object, and consider only its capacity of satisfying human wants, we have what is called its worth or value. This value of the thing, — the psychological fact which is left, when all the qualities marking the objective thing are reduced to their social efficiency — is the notion, of which the currency is the representation, reducing thought to the level of the senses, and embodying the ' ideality ' of value in a tangible and visible object. So long as this ' idea ' of value is kept in view, the cur rency is comprehended : but when the perception of the notion disappears, money is left a mere piece of cur rency, the general notion being narrowed down to the coinage. Thus the notion of money, like other notions in their ideal truth, is not in us, nor in the things merely : it is what from a minor point of view, when we and the things are regarded under the head of want or need, may be called the truth of both, the unity of the two sides. Thus considered, money falls into its proper place in the order of things. CHAPTER XXIV. FROM SUBSTANCE TO SUBJECT. '!T is; in my view; all important/ says Hegel1, 'to apprehend and express the True not as Substance, but equally much as Subject.' Substance, as Spinoza defines it, is that which is in itself and which is con ceived through itself, something which does not need the conception of something else by which its concept may be formed 2. Substance, in other words, is something which serves to explain itself, which is causa sui. The mind, looking out on the wide world of mutable and manifold objects, finds its rest in the great calm of a something at their base, the eternal nature which, itself unmoved, is the one foundation, complete and sufficient, of all things, — a res aeterna et infmita, which can feed the mind with joy alone3. These words suggest only an object — a transcendent object — the basis of an objective order. They seem to leave little for the con templating subject to do save to discern it and, so dis cerning, to rest in it and to love. They seem to leave substance a mere datum, a far-off all-embracing end in which the variety of human effort can find a central object and a final close. Yet, in the end it appears 4 that this Res aeterna loves himself with an intellectual 1 Hegel, Werke, ii. 14. 2 Spinoza, Eth. Def. 3. 3 Spin. De intell. Em. \. 10. * Spin. Eth. v. 35. 336 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. love, and this love is identified with the love of man to God, so far at least as man's mind, considered sub specie aeternitatis, can be said to 'explicate' Deity. From this conclusion it might be said that Spinoza rises above the mere category of substance : God is no longer the mere foundation of things — the absolute object of all objects. He rises in human spirit (regarded in its eternal significance) to the rank of a true subject. He is not merely known as the True ; but He himself, living and moving in the essential spirit of man, knows himself and acquiesces in his infinite beatitude. But if this be the legitimate inference to be drawn from the closing sections of the Ethics, it is not the view ordinarily suggested by the mention of Spinoza's doctrine. That doctrine, on the contrary, seems, as it first confronts us, and as it has taken its place in history, to omit the subjectivity which had found so decided a recognition in the commencement of Cartesianism. In the cogito ergo sum so much at least is clearly stated : true being —the true — is not merely known, but itself knows ; not a mere object, but a subject : a subject-object, or, an Idea. It is to be admitted, indeed, that Descartes hardly remains at this altitude, but he touches it for a moment. Even when he finds in the conception of God a security for truth and reality, and thus seems to base these on a one-sidedly objective standard, he regards God as, on the other hand, the truth and reality postulated and presupposed by the structural system of our ideas. God — such seems the tendency of his so-called 'proof — is the inevitable prius and presupposition of our thought and being : He makes us know, as much as He is ultimately the object known: He is the unity and the creator of subject and object. But it is hardly possible to get in philosophy the full recognition of the antithesis between subject and sub- xxiv.] SPINOZA. 337 stance and the inclusion of both in the fuller Idea, till after the time of Kant. Kant himself is, in essentials, the antithesis of Spinoza, but it is not till Fichte that the full force of that antithesis is expressly recognised. With Hegel, the two opposite points of view are equally insisted on : the immanence and the transcendence of the True, the Real, the Absolute : or, in other words, the unity in it of subject and object, or of thought and existence. Or, in the words of the religious spirit, though heaven and the heaven of heavens cannot contain Him, He dwells in the spirit of the righteous, and is not far from any one of us. The truth is not the correspond ence or agreement of an idea with a further reality which it represents. Such an idea or ' representation ' is a projection which has escaped from our hands, which has slipped from our grip, and which, while owning its mere vicarious character, at the same time beckons us on to seek a reality we can never find. The ' representation J is in a way objective — it is set over against us: but yet it is not truly objective, not self-subsistent and self-possessed. Its objectivity is the objectivity of a name : a quasi-objectivity, which requires to be dipped in the living waters of intelligence before it can really exist and act. It seems, to the untrained observer, to point only outwards to the real object which it copies or designates : to a deeper re flection, it is seen to point equally inward to the mind which informed it and projected it. Thus the knowing subject, and the known object, with the representation which acts as a perpetual mediator to connect and yet not unify the one of these terms with the other, — all at last take their place, reduced and transfigured, in the unity of the Idea. According to the Spinozist point of view, thought, it might seem by a sort of miracle, dispels the mists that z 338 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. envelop and bewilder it, sees through the multeity of modes, and the isolated pictures of imagination, to the true reality, one, infinite and eternal. Before that august vision of absolute wholeness the only attitude of a finite mind would seem to be resignation, worship, reverence, — deeply shading into the submission of absorption. For in it intellect and will are declared to have no place *. With such a statement, we get that first aspect of religion which has found its most imposing representative in the faith of Islam. In every religion there must, however, be more than this : or it would fail to do what all religion essentially does. Sheer dependence— Schlechthinnige Abhangigkeit (as Schleiermacher has named it)— can never be the whole burden of a religious teacher's message. Always — at least in the background— there is a contradictory element — in apparent discrepancy with the first — the deification of the worshipper. And as the Ethics of Spinoza — like every complete system of speculative truth— deals with a problem parallel to, if not even identical with, that of religion, its initial definitions and main programme must never let us forget the tacit pre suppositions worked out to explicitness, as they are partly, in its conclusion. When Intellect and Will are denied to the Deiis—Natura — Substantia, it is meant that the Absolute is and has more than intellect and will can well name, and that in Him (or Her, or It, for the pronominal distinctions of gender matter nothing here), the separation of will from intellect is a fallacy which can have no place. What Spinoza casts out are the lower passions, the affections of weakness ; these as such, i. e. as elements of weakness, can have no place in Him. But in God, as in the free man who most resembles God, and in whose love He loves himself, 1 Eth. i. 17 schol. SPINOZA, 339 there is— but that also in terms we cannot fathom- abundance of joy— the joy of infinite self-realisation. Partly by the complementary theory of Leibniz, partly by the antagonist theories of Kant, the way had been prepared for setting forth, and in fuller outline, the implications so tardily admitted by Spinoza. It was only by a misuse or mal-extension of a word that Herder's God — a God who is Force — and the Force of Forces — could be supposed an advance upon Spinoza. There is in Force an analogue of Life ; but it is life in dependence, life not self-centred, always going forth, and when it goes forth dissipated. It is as it were pushed from behind, and is lost in what comes after it. If a Force of Forces means anything, it means some thing more than Force: it means a master of force, a force-controller and force-adjuster, a unity and principle of forces. And Substance, as Spinoza under stood it, is more than this variability, this deification of instability. It is the unity in which the variety and disparity of existence, the multiplicity of vicissitude, is merged and lost, only again to issue from it, and yet not leave it behind, in the infinitely-various modes of its two great and conspicuous attributes of conscious ness and extensionality. If Hegel then sought to go beyond Spinoza, he sought to find a formula which would lose nothing that Spinoza had reached, but would at the same time bring out what Spinoza had left an implication, or noted in a partial rectification. As in religion, besides the utter dependence on God (so that, God failing, I perish), there must be also an absolute union, complete reconciliation — complete as culminating in unity and identity (so that God shall not be God, unless I am I): so it is in philosophy. The Absolute cannot merely be, and be far away — the last goal in which the variety of life is made one, and z 2 340 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. the turmoil of the passionate existences laid to rest. The Soul which is (as some of the medieval Christians would say) still in itinere, a wayfarer, is such because its glance is turned on outward circumstances : but country is no accident : the soul even here carries with it that patria, ' which is the heavenly/ in its longings, and has it, even while yet on pilgrimage, in that strong possession of all things by itself, which the theologian styles Faith. This goal determines the pilgrimage, fixes its direction, gives progress to its steps. In the myth-loving language of Plato (and of Words worth in his Platonic ode) the Soul has in other spheres of being dwelt with the gods and seen the secret of the world : it is itself one of the immortals, and as it is here and now, is in a land of exile. At the morning of birth, the living sample of humanity has left his original glory behind; and a deep forgetfulness— only short of absolute — cuts it off from his every-day consciousness. In his present reality he finds himself in a land of darkness, fast bound in a hollow of the rock, looking out only on the ghostly images that flit across his prison wall, cast there by the objects that move between his back and the light of a mysterious fire behind him and them. Such is his natural estate, as it meets the bodily eye : the estate of the lowly savage, whom superstition and ignorance seem to hold as their cap tive for ever. But, though his high home and his glory of other days have left no conscious memory in the soul, asleep and imbruted in its fleshly house, they have not departed without leaving a trace behind. For forgetfulness is not blank non-existence. The sample of humanity inherits the birthright of his fathers — he has hopes and fears, duties and rights, which are his, if he can mature himself to take possession of them. He xxiv.] THE PLATONIC MYTH. 341 suffers from the pains of growth, from the sense of disparity between what he is and what he may and should be — from the noble uneasiness and dissatisfac tion of a being who feels — if he does not know — his infinite potentialities. For these potentialities— other wise they have no title even to that name — are also actualities, yet actualities which protest their own in completeness, and crave imperiously for what they lack. What he has is his right, but his right only in so far as it is also his duty. It is as such, and only as such, that he still retains the soul in all its prerogatives : as the right, which is the duty, of knowledge. Such a pre-figured and promised, but yet to be realised, possession is what Plato has called Eros, or Love. But it is a Love whose wings are at first invisible, and who often seems rather to crawl among ignoble things than to soar in the free fresh air. The process of experience has been by Plato called Anamnesis or Recollection. But Recollection is not always an easy, and never a merely passive, process ; and sometimes the forgetfulness seems so deep that no extraneous stimulus can at all move it. We have seen already one of these stimuli which rouse the sleeping sense — the mystery of numbers : and there are many others. But, we have also learned, that in the psychical sphere items of memory are not, as reckless fancy puts it, stored up in compartments, sorted and arranged, ready to be pulled out. The process of recollection is a complicated affair : an affair of give and take, of comparison and selection and rejection, of construction and reconstruction. You cannot haul up ready-made memories from the mine. And this perhaps was some times forgotten by Plato ; it certainly has been by more than one of his commentatprs. You may, no doubt, call up ideas from the vasty deep : but they come by laws 342 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. and principles of their own. Even when they come, which they sometimes do unexpectedly, they come as an echo of the calling mind. Recollection involves intellectual process : as Kant said, the synthesis of imagination reposes upon the synthesis in the concept. Yet— and this is the point which Plato's title of Anamnesis accentuates— unless ' the soul had been such as to be affected in this way ' (the words are those of Aristotle), unless the soul had been implicitly intellectual in tone and faculty, it would not have grasped the presented universe under the categories which it uses. There is, says Aristotle, in the barest act of sensation a congenital power of judgment ; there is, says Plato, an eye of the soul— a natural virtue of intelligence, which can never be put into it, and must always be presupposed in any theory of its processes. There are, therefore, no innate ideas, says Cudworth in explanation of Plato, if these ideas mean formed and completed products of knowledge. All ideas in this sense begin and grow within the range of experi ence, and the history of their growth or development in literature and art can be at least approximately traced. We can trace, that is, the successions and connexions of the various types of beauty, or goodness : can show how the idea at one time dwelt in one of its aspects, at another in a different one. We can observe the variation, and it may be the progress, in men's con ception of God. But it is another matter when we seek to explain these ideas themselves out of other elements, heterogeneous to them. When that question is asked, then with Plato we seem, in the absence of any theory of origins, obliged to own that it is by the Beautiful that beautiful things come to be beautiful. The M6ra£acrt9 fls «XXo yews — the crossing of essential boundaries— which Aristotle forbids to science, still xxiv.] ULTIMATE CATEGORIES. 343 raises its eternal barrier in the logical, if it cease to hold good (as has been suggested) in the physical sphere. In the totality which we call the world and experience of reality there are, so to say, ultimate and irreducible provinces. The utmost that philosophy, i. e. science, can do with these is to co-ordinate them,— to show their mutual filiations, adaptations, and har monies, — to note their inadequacies and discrepancies. They are not all of equal rank, perhaps ; they have to yield to each other, it may be in turn : but none of them can be arbitrarily expunged from the totality, and none of them shown to be a mere phase of others. To do that is to strip the universe of its variety and — it may be added — of its beauty and its interest. If it be a false philosophy that does it, there is a good deal of false philosophy abroad. There is a lust of ex planation which is never content till it has found an equation for everything, till it has expressed every thing in terms of the common-place, till it has emptied everything of all that made it individual and real, and turned it into an abstract, identical (as only abstracts can be) with some other abstract. Such abstractions are of course useful, and therefore need no excuse, when restricted to a special sphere. So long, that is, as we remember that it is an abstraction we are making, and that we are arbitrarily simplifying the real natural problem, no harm is done by these artificial construc tions ; and they are important steps in a larger process. But what is correct and useful within a range whose limits we can define, becomes dangerous when carried beyond all bounds. Its approximate truth then becomes misleading error. It is these irreducible elements — these great provinces in human experience, in reality, in the system of reason — that correspond to the more important of what 344 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. are known as Platonic ideas. As ultimate constituents of the actual world they are in the narrower sense inexplicable. One does not amount to an exact sum of some others, nor is one got from another by the simple process of subtraction. But if they cannot be explained, by being reduced to multiples of some one basis, they can be comprehended in the respective implication and explication they exhibit with their co- realities. They can be correlated, reduced, and unified : we may even say, they can be identified ; but if we use such a term, we must mean that there is some totality beyond and above them in which they all find a place and all are harmonious ; in which all when brought to their Truth are really one and the same. This birth right of human nature in all ages and countries — this central essence of man's spirit — is the realm of Platonic ideas. They are the great elements, or constituent members, of humanity and of reality : the framework of his mind and of the world. How in each case they may be wrought out in detail, to what degree they may here be evolved, and there stunted, is a matter of historical research. And, in a sense, even it is not wrong to try to trace them one to another : to explain them, as the phrase is, one by another. For they are essentially connected : they are members of one system : they are unified and harmonised in a way for which even the word 'organism ' is wholly insufficient. They are the poles and lines on which the tent of human life, of intelligent life, is stretched : but they are also the invisible ties which bind together the earth and heavens, and all that is therein. These ideas therefore are immanent in man : for they are the basis of human nature. But to name, to dis entangle them, to measure out their bounds and describe their connexions— that is no easy work. And that is xxiv.] PLATONISM. 345 the work of Platonic recollection. That is the process of historical experience. But it is a small thing for Plato to say that these ideas are innate in man. What he is more concerned to make clear is that in the possession or vision of these eternal forms, the human soul is a partner of the gods, a citizen of the heavens. In less mythical language, man, as an intelligent, artistic, moral, and religious being, is not a mere accidental on-looker on the surface of things, but near their central and abiding truth. The forms of his mind, to speak after the manner of Kant, are the objective essences of the real world of experience. Degrees there may be in the reality which they possess — less or larger measures of truth to full experience — but true and real they are : never mere falsity or emptiness. To estimate the amounts of that reality is a problem Plato often tried. At one time it seems as if the Good were in his estimate the form of forms, the real of reals : but when we look closely, we see that it is a goodness which is synonymous with real reality or perfect being. At another time truth, i. e. reality, seems to be lord of all : at another, beauty : and again he seems to confess his inability to lay down the order of precedence in this hierarchy. Of one thing only he is perfectly clear : and that is the unreality, the non-entity of the sense-world as merely perceived, and the true being of the world of reason. But he has no doubts as to the central truth that in the good, the true, and the beautiful, there is a higher reality — a more far-reaching and deep-piercing influence than in all the mere variety of sensation, the mere multitude of sensible fact. What Plato has sometimes called the act of remi niscence, what he has sometimes called the instinct of Love, is also known to him as the process of Dialectic. For reminiscence has to watch and wrestle with the 346 PROLEGOMENA. [xxiv. inertia of oblivion, has to set the imagined beside the real, and to correct percepts by concepts, concepts by percepts, has to brace up its energies, and to advance not by mere pressing onward, but by tacking and zig zagging through contrary difficulties finally realise itself. And love too is a battle, where the craving for union has to measure its force with the instinct of inde pendence, where selfishness and self-surrender seek a reconciliation, and where in the close, if the close be love, each is self-retained only as self-abandoned, and each rises to a higher union in which lower selfhoods are absorbed. Even so in the course of Dialectic. It is the art which divides and conjoins, which unifies and distinguishes : the art of asking and answering. To Plato it appears in the main as an action of the in telligent subject : but an action which, as he hints, is almost a natural instinct, which through discipline has become an art. In the hands of its typical artist, it proceeds, or seems to proceed, as if unconscious of its principle and end. Socrates has, as he professes, no overt conception of the result : he has no knowledge of the positive conclusion to be reached. It is the Logos —the logic of reality— which sustains the movement. Abandoning any subjective humour of carrying the argument to a preconceived end; one is swept on by the current of real logic— the reason in things. The dogma we have set up and seemed to see before us, will, if we are dispassionate, carry us on beyond itself, and suggest aspects calling for recognition and accept ance. If only we refrain from arresting the movement of criticism, — a course to which prudence, ease, custom, and every form of the ignava ratio counsel us,— truth will reveal itself in us, and by us. It is because other aims, personal and particular, are so ever-present with us, that speculative free inquiry seems so hard. It is X XIV.] PL A TON ISM. 347 we who insist on closing up the door, not the truth that is reluctant to show itself. Truth, then, is self-revelation or development. Not a result which is to be accepted, bowed to, and reve renced : but the result issuing (and only valuable as issuing) from a process in which we and objectivity are fellow-workers. The truth may no doubt be presented —as Spinoza does present it — in definitions, stating the net result as fundamental fact. Fundamental fact it is ; but as so stated, as Substance, it comes as a stranger, almost as an enemy : the great vision, suddenly offered to untrained eyes, overwhelms and alarms the living sense of self, of personality. Hegel wishes to show it as a friend, as our very own,— as Subject (but not merely subject). It is for this that philosophy runs through its cycle and returns into itself. Man points to nature and nature to man : universal to individual : thought to things: the self to God, and God to the human soul. CHAPTER XXV. REASON AND THE DIALECTIC OF UNDERSTANDING. REPRESENTATIVE conceptions, besides being the burden of our ordinary materialising consciousness, are also the data of science, accepted and developed in their consequences. Because they are so accepted, as given into our hand, scientific reasoning can only insti tute relations between them. Its business as thus conceived is progressive unification, comparing objects with one another, demonstrating the similarities which exist between them, and combining them with each other. The exercise of thought which deals with such objects is limited by their existence : it is only formal. It is finite thought, because it is only subjective : it begins at a given point and stops somewhere, and never gets quite round its materials so as to call them truly its own. Each of the objects on which it is turned seems to be outside of it, and independent of it. Each point of fact, again, when it is carried out to its utmost, meets with other thoughts which limit it, and claim to be equally self-centred. Such knowledge creeps on from point to point. To this thinking German philosophy from the time of Kant and Jacobi applied a name, which since the days of Coleridge has been translated by l Understanding1.' This degree or mode of thinking 1 'Verstand.' UNDERSTANDING. 349 — not a faculty of thought — is the systematised and thorough exercise of what in England is called ' Common Sense/ In the first place, it is synonymous with prac tical intelligence. It takes what it calls facts, or things, as given, and aims only at arranging and combining them and drawing from them counsels of prudence or rules of art. Seeing things on a superficies, as it were so many unconnected points, here itself and there the. various things of the world, it tries to bring them into connexion. It accepts existing distinctions, and seeks to render them more precise by pointing out and sifting the elements of sameness. Its greatest merit is an abhor rence of vagueness, inconsistency, and what it stigmatises as mysticism : it wishes to be clear, distinct, and prac tical. In its proper sphere, — and it has an indis pensable function to perform even in philosophy : wherever, that is, it is unnecessary to go into the essential truth of things, and one has only to do good work in a clearly defined sphere, — the understanding has an independent value of its own *. Nor is this true merely of practical life, where a man must accommodate himself to facts : it is equally applicable in the higher theoretic life,--in art, religion, and philosophy. If intelligent definiteness does not make itself apparent in these, there is something wrong about them. It is only when this exercise of thought is regarded as a ne plus ultra, and its mandates to restrict inves tigation by the limits of foregone conclusions find obedience, that understanding deserves the reproachful language which was lavished upon it by the German philosophers at the close of the last century. The understanding is abstract : this sums up its offences in one word. Its objects, that is the things it deals with 1 ' Die Vernunft ohne Verstand ist Nichts ; der Verstand doch Etwas ohne Vernunft.' Hegel's Leben, p. 546. 350 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. and believes utterly real, are only partly so, and when that incompleteness is unrecognised, are only abstrac tions. Both in its contracted forms, such as faith and common sense, and in its systematic form, the logical or narrowly-consistent intellect, it is partial and liable to be tenacious of half-truths. Only that whereas in feeling and common-sense there is often a great deal which they cannot express, — whereas the heart is often more liberal than its interpreting mind will allow — the reverse is true of the logically-consistent intellect. The narrowness of the latter is, in its own opinion, exactly equal to the truth of things : and whatever it expresses is asserted without qualification to be the absolute fact. Its business is, given the initial point (which is assumed to be certain and perspicuous), to see all which that point will necessarily involve or lead to. For example, Order may be supposed to be the chief end of the State. Let us consider, says the intelligent arguer (without wasting time on abstruse inquiries as to what Order is or means, and what sort of Order we want), to what consequences and institutions this con ception will lead us. Or, again, the chief end of the State is assumed to be Liberty. To what special forms of organisation will this hypothesis (also assumed a self-evident conception) lead ? Or we may go a step further. It is evident, some will say, that in a State there must be a certain admixture of Order and Liberty. How are we to proceed — what laws and ordinances will be necessary, to secure the proper equilibrium of these two principles ? The two must be blended, and each have its legitimate influence. These are examples of the operation of Understand ing. It can only reach a synthesis (or conjunction), never a real unity, because it believes in the omni potence of the abstractions with which it began : but XXV.] UNDERSTANDING. 35* must either carry out one partial principle to its conse quences, or allow an alternate and combined force to two opposite principles. Its canon is identity: given something, let us see what follows when we keep the same point always in view, and compare other points with the one which we are supposed to know. Its method is analytic : given a conception in which popu lar thought supposes itself at home, and let us see all the elements of truth which can be deduced from it. Its statements are abstract and narrow : or, in the words of Anaxagoras, one thing is cut off from another with a hatchet1. In its excess it degenerates into dogmatism, whether that dogmatism be theological or naturalistic. The fact is that the Understanding, as this analytic, abstract, and finite action of mind is called, — the thought which holds objective ideas distinct from one another, and from the subjective faculties of thought as a whole,— that this Understanding is, when it claims to be heard and obeyed in science, not suffi ciently thorough-going. It begins at a point which is not so isolated as it seems, but is a member of a body of thought : nor is it aware that the whole of this body of thought is in organic, and even more than organic, union. It errs in taking too much for granted : and in not seeing how this given point is the result of a pro cess, — that in it, in any thought or idea, several tenden cies or elements converge and are held in union, but with the possibility of working their way into a new independence. In other words, the Understanding requires, as the organon and method of philosophy, to be replaced by the Reason 2, — by infinite thought, On ov Kex&piffTai d\\rjAuv ra cv T$> kvi Koa^a ov5t a.TTOK(KoiiTai Simplic. Phys. fol. 383 (ed. Diels, p. 176). Vernunft.' 352 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. concrete, at once analytic and synthetic. How then, it may be asked, can we make the passage from the inadequate to the adequate ? To that question the answer may be given that it is our act of arbitrary arrest which halts at the inadequate : that in complete Reason, which is the constituent nature both of us and of things, the Understanding is only a grade which points beyond itself, and therefore presupposes and struggles up to the adequate thought. In other words, it is Reason which creates or lays down for behoof of its own organisation the aims, conditions, and fixed entities, —the objects, by which it is bound and limited in its analytic exercise as understanding. Reason, therefore, is the implicit tendency to correct its own inadequacy : and we have only to check self-will and prejudice so far that the process may be accomplished. The movement is not at one step : it has a middle term or mean which often seems as if it were a step backward. Progress in knowledge is usually described as produced by the mode of demonstration or the mode of experience. Formal Logic prefers the first mode of describing it : Applied Logic prefers the -second. Either mode may serve, if we properly comprehend what demonstration and experience mean. And that will not be done unless we keep equally before us the affirmative and the negative element in the process. The law of rational progress in knowledge, of the dialectical movement of consciousness, or in one word of experience, is not simple movement in a straight line, but movement by negation and absorption of the premisses. The conclusion or the new object of know ledge is a product into which the preceding object is reduced or absorbed. Thus the movement from faith (which is concentrated and wholly personal knowledge) to open and universal knowledge, which is capable of '•] DIALECTIC. 353 becoming the possession of a community,— truth and not merely conviction, must pass through doubt. The pre misses from which we start, and the original object with which we begin, are not left in statu quo: they are destroyed in their own shape, and become only mate rials to build up a new object and a conclusion. It is on the stepping-stones of discarded ideas that we rise to higher truth : and it is on the abrogation of the old objects of knowledge that the new objects are founded. Not merely does a new object come in to supplement the old, and correct its inadequacies by the new presence : not merely do we add new ranges to our powers of vision, retaining the old faculties and subjoining others. The whole world— alike inward and outward,— the consciousness and its object— is subjected to a thorough renovation : every feature is modified, and the system re-created. The old perishes: but in perishing contributes to constitute the new. Thus the new is at once the affirmation and negation of the old. And such is the invariable nature of intelli gent progress, of which the old and not a few modern logicians failed to render a right account, because they missed the negative element, and did not see that the immediate premisses must be abolished in order to secure a conclusion,— even as the grapes must be crushed before the wine can be obtained. This is the real meaning of Experience, when it is called the teacher of humanity: and it was for this reason that Bacon described it as 'far the best demonstration V Experience is that absolute process, embracing both us and things, which displays the nullity of what is immediately given, or baldly and nakedly accepted, and completes it by the rough remedy of contradiction. The change comes over both 1 Novunt Organum, Book I. 70. A a 354 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. us and the things : neither the one side nor the other is left as it was before. And it is here that the advantage of Experience over demonstration consists. Demonstration tends to be looked upon as subjective only (constringit assensum, non res} : whereas Expe rience is also objective. But Experience is more than merely objective : it is the absolute process of thought pure and entire ; and as such it is described by Hegel as Dialectic, or Dialectical movement. This Dialectic covers the ground of demonstration, — a fragment of it especially described and emphasised in the Formal Logic,— and of Experience,— under which name it is better known in actual life, and in the philosophy of the sciences1. Dialectic is the negative or destructive aspect of reason, as preparatory to its affirmative or construc tive aspect. It is the spirit of dissent and criticism : the outgoing as opposed to the indwelling : the restless as distinguished from the quiet: the reproductive as opposed to the nutritive instinct: the centrifugal as opposed to the centripetal force : the radical and pro gressive tendency as opposed to the conservative. But no one of these examples sufficiently or accurately describes it. For it is the utterance of an implicit contradiction, — the recognition of an existing and felt, but hitherto unrecognised and unformulated want. Dialectic does not supervene from without upon the fixed ideas of understanding : it is the evidence of the higher nature which lies behind them, of the dependence on a larger unity which understanding implicitly or explicitly denies. That higher nature, the notion or grasp of reasonable thought, comes forward, and has at first, in opposition to the one-sided products of understanding, the look of a destructive agent. If 1 Phenomenologie des Getsfes, p. 67. XXV.] DIALECTIC. 355 we regard the understanding and its object, as ultimate and final, — and they are so regarded in the ordinary estimation of the world,— then this negative action of reason seems utterly pernicious, and tends to end in the subversion of all fixity whatever, of everything definite. In this light Dialectic is what is commonly known as Scepticism ; just as the understanding in its excess is known as Dogmatism. But in the total grasp of the rational or speculative notion, Dialectic ceases to be Scepticism, and Understanding ceases to be Dogmatism. Still there can be no doubt that the Dialectic of reason is dangerous, if taken abstractly and as if it were a whole truth. For the thoughts of ordinary men tend to be more abstract than their materials warrant. Men seek to formulate their feelings, faith, and con duct: but the rationale of their inmost belief,— their creed,— is generally narrower than it might be. Out of the undecomposed and massive 'substance,' on which their life and conduct is founded, they extract one or two ingredients : they emphasise with undue stress one or two features in their world, and attach to these partial formulae a value which would be deserved only if they really represented the whole facts. Hence when the narrow outlines of their creed are submitted to dialectic,— when the inlying contradictions are ex posed, men feel as if the system of the world had sunk beneath them. But it is not the massive structure of their world, the organic unity in which they live, that is struck by dialectic : it is only those luminous points, the representative terms of material thought, which float before their consciousness, and which have been formulated in hard and fast outlines by the under standing. These points, as so defined and exaggerated, are what dialectic shakes. Not an alien force, but the A a 2 356 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. inherent power of thought, destroys the temporary constructions of the understanding. The infinite comes to show the inadequacy of the finite which it has made. In philosophy this second stage is as essential as the first. The one-sidedness of the first abstraction is corrected by the one-sidedness of the other. In the Philosophy of Plato, as has been noted, the dialectical energy of thought is sometimes spoken of under the analogy of sexual passion— the Love which, in the words of Sophocles, 'falls upon possessions' and makes all fixed ordinance of no account, and finds no obstacles insuperable to its strong desire. But Love, as the speaker explains, is a child of Wealth and Want : he is never poor, and never rich : he is in a mean between ignorance and knowledge1. Thus is described the active unrest of growth, the ' inquietude poussante,' as Leibniz called it,— the quickening force of the nega tive and of contradiction. At the word ' contradiction ' there is heard a mur mur of objection, partly on technical, partly on material grounds. There are, it is said, other ways of getting from one idea to another than by contradiction : and it is not right to give the title to mere cases of contrast and correlation. Now it may be the case that the rela tions of ideas are many and various. In particular there is to many people a decided pleasure in the mere accumulation of bits of knowledge. In their mental stock there are only aggregates,— conjunctions due to accidents of time and place, — associations and fusions which do not reach organised unity. In all of us, perhaps, there are more or less miscellaneous collec tions of beliefs, perceptions, hopes, and wishes, in no very obvious connexion with one another. An united self, one, harmonious, and complete, is probably rather 1 Plato, Symposion, 203. xxv.] CONTRADICTION. 357 an ideal of development than a fact realised. There are in each two or three discordant selves, — among which it might sometimes be difficult to select the right and true one (for that will depend on the momen tary point of view). The deeper consciousness may go on entirely independent of the train of the more super ficial ideas : the world of reality may glide past without touching the world of dream or of fiction : our business part may live in a region parted off from our religion by gulfs inscrutable. In all these cases there cannot be said to be any contradiction. But Hegel speaks of the essential progress of know ledge, and of that true self or real mind which has attained complete harmony— the self and mind that is implicitly or explicitly Absolute. In such a mind where the finite has passed or is passing into the infinite, in a mind that is really becoming one and total, its parts must meet and modify each other. At each phase, if that phase is earnest, self-certain, and real, it claims to be complete, and can brook no rival. The bringer of new things must appear as an enemy : for the old system, however imperfect as a mere form, has behind it the strength of an infinite and perfect content : it is more than it has explicated : but as it (from its imper fection and honesty) identifies itself with its form, it is resolved to resist change. Progress then must be by antagonism : it cannot be real progress otherwise, but only the mere shifting of dilettante doubt and dilettante toleration. Both new and old are worth something, and they must prove their value by neither being lost, but both recognised, in a completer scheme of things. Yet there is a difference in the measure of contra diction at different stages of thought. It is always greatest when there is least to be opposed about. The more meagre an idea, a creed, a term of thought, 358 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. the more violent the antitheses to it. The more abstractly we hold a doctrine, the more readily are we disposed to sniff opposition. And as in more concrete belief, so in the more abstract terms of thought. They seem so wide apart— like ' Is ' and ' Is not '—and yet, taken alone, they are really so ready to recoil into one another. As thought deepens, contradiction takes a more modified form. The relativity of things becomes apparent : and what were erewhile opposed as contra dictory, turn out as pairs of correlatives, neither of which is fully what it professed to be, unless it also is all that seemed reserved for the other. Lastly, and in the full truth of development, progress is seen to be not merely a sudden recoil from one abstraction to another, nor merely a continual reference to an underlying correlative, but the movement of one totality which advances by self-opposition, self-reconciliation, and self- reconstruction. In this stage, the weight and bulk of unity keeps the contradiction in its place of due sub ordination. But both elements are equally essential, and if the unity is less palpable in the abstract begin nings, and the divergence less wide at the close, at neither beginning nor close can either be absent. But if we merely look at the differentiation or nega tion involved in the action of reason, we miss the half of its meaning : and the new statement is as one-sided as the old. We have not grasped the full meaning until we see that what, as understanding, affirmed a finite, denies, as dialectic, the absoluteness or ade quacy of that finite. Both the partial views have a right to exist, because each gives its contribution to the science of truth \ If we penetrate behind the surface, —if we do not look at the two steps in the process abstractly and in separation, — it will be seen that these 1 Cf. Dante, Farad, iv. 130. XXV.] THE UNITY OF CONTRADICTIONS. 359 two elements coincide and unite. But we must be careful here. This coincidence or identification of oppo- sites has not annihilated their opposition or difference. That difference subsists, but in abeyance, reduced to an element or ' moment ' in the unity. Each of the two elements has been modified by the union : and thus when each issues from the unity it has a richer significance than it had before. This unity, in which difference is lost and found, is the rational notion, — the speculative grasp of thought. It is the product of experience, — the ampler affirmative which is founded upon an inclusion of negatives. We began with the bare unit, or simple and un- analysed point, which satisfied popular language and popular imagination as its nucleus : — the representation which had caught and half-idealised a point, moment, or aspect in the range of feeling and sensation. In this stage the notion or thought proper is yet latent. In the first place, the nucleus of imagination was analysed, defined, and, as we may surmise, narrowed in the Intellect. And this grade of thought is known as the Understanding. In the second place, the definite and precise term, as understanding supposes it, was sub jected to criticism : its contradictions displayed ; and the very opposite of the first definition established in its place. This is the action of Dialectic. In the third place, by means of this second stage, the real nature or truth was seen to lie in a union where the opposites interpenetrate and mould each other. Thus we have as a conscious unity, — conscious because it, as unity, yet embraces a difference as difference— what we started with as an unconscious unity, the truth of feeling, faith, and inspiration. The first was an immediate unity :— that is to say, we were in the midst of the unity, sunk in it, and making a part of it : the second is a mediated 360 PROLEGOMENA. [xxv. unity, which has been reached by a process of reflec tion, and which as a conscious unity involves that process. Reason, then, is infinite, as opposed to understand ing, which is finite thinking. The limits which are found and accepted by the analytic intellect, are limits which reason has imposed, and which it can take away : the limits are in it, and not over it. The larger reason has been laying down those limits, which our little minds at first tend to suppose absolute. Let us put the same law in more concrete terms. It is reason, — the Idea, — or, to give it an inadequate and abstract name, Natural Selection — which has created the several forms of the animal and vegetable world : it is reason, again, which in the struggle for existence contradicts the very inadequacies which it has brought into being: and it is reason, finally, which affirms both these actions, — the hereditary descent, and the adaptation— in the provisionally permanent and adequate forms which result from the struggle. The three stages thus enumerated are therefore not merely stages in our human reason as subjective. They state the law of rational development in pure thought, in Nature, and in the world of Mind, — the world of Art, Morals, and Science. They represent the law of thought or reason in its most general or abstract terms. They state, mainly in reference to the method or form of thought, that Triplicity, which will be seen in those real formations or phases to which thought moulds itself, — the typical species of reason. They reappear hundreds of times, in different multiples, in the system of philosophy. The abstract point of the Notion which parts asunder in the Judgment, and returns to a unity including difference in the Syllo gism : — the mere generality of the Universal, which, XXV.] DIALECTIC. 361 by a disruption into Particulars and detail, gives rise to the real and actual Individual : — the Identity which has to be combined with Difference in order to furnish a possible Ground for Existence : — the baldness and nakedness of an Immediate belief, which comes to the full and direct certainty of itself, to true immediacy, only by gathering up the full sense of the antithesis which can separate conviction from truth, or by real ising the Mediation connecting them : — all these are illustrations of the same law really applied which has been formally stated as the necessity for a defining, a dialectical, and a speculative element in thought. The three parts of Logic are an instance of the same thing: and when the Idea, or organism of thought, appears developed in the series of Natural forms, it is only to prepare the kingdom of reason actualised in the world of Mind. The Understanding, on the field of the world, corresponds, says Hegel ', to the concep tion of Divine Goodness. The life of nature goes on in the independence and self-possession of all its parts, each as fixed and proud of its own, as if its share of earth were for ever assured. The finite being then has his season of self-satisfied ease : while the gods live in quiet, away from the sight of man's doings. The dia lectical stage, again, corresponds to the conception of God as an omnipotent Lord : when the Power of the universe waxes terrific, destroying the complacency of the creatures and making them feel their insufficiency, —when the once beneficent appears jealous and cruel, and the joyous equanimity of human life is oppressed by the terrors of the inscrutable hand of fate. The easy-minded Greek lived for the most part in the former world: the uneasy Hebrew to a great extent in the latter. But the truth lay neither in the placid 1 See in the Logic (vol. ii. p. 145). 362 PROLEGOMENA. wisdom of Zeus, leaving the world to its own devices, nor in the jealous Jehovah of Mount Sinai: the true speculative union is found in the mystical unity of Godhead with human nature. In this comprehensive spirit did Hegel treat Logic. This Triplicity runs through Hegel's works. If you open one, the main divisions are marked with the capitals A, B; C. One of these, it may be, is broken up into chapters headed by the Roman numerals I, II, III. Under one or more of these probably come severally the Arabic numerals i, 2, 3. Any one of these again may be subdivided, and gives rise to sections, headed by the small letters a, b, c. And, lastly, any one of these may be treated to a distribution under the three titles a, 0, y. Of course the division is not in each case carried equally far: nor does the subject always permit it: nor is Hegel's knowledge alike vigorous, or his interest in all directions the same. PROLEGOMENA BOOK III LOGICAL OUTLINES PROLEGOMENA CHAPTER XXVI. THOUGHT PURE AND ENTIRE. THE English reader may probably be taken to be familiar with the conception of Logic as the Science of the Form of Thought. He may also have heard this explained as equivalent to the Science of Thought as Thought, or of Thought as Form, or of Formal Thought. But, probably, also, he brings to' the lesson no very high estimate of form as such. In the old language of Greek philosophy, transmitted through the Schoolmen of the West, and still lingering in the phraseology of Bacon and Shakespeare l, Forms and substantial forms were powers in the world of reality. But a generation arose which knew them not : to which they were only belated survivals of the past. The forms had lost connexion with matter and content, and had come to seem some thing occult, transcendent, and therefore, to a practical and realistic age, something fantastic and superfluous. Yet it may be well to recall that the same author who has put on record his view that forms are only mental figments, unless they be fully ' determinate in matter/ has equally laid it down that the so-called ' causes ' of vulgar philosophy— the matter and the agent— are only 1 E.g. 'formal' in Hamlet, iv. 5. 215; 'informal' in Measure for Measure, v. 236. 366 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. * vehicles of the form.' Thus spontaneously did Bacon reconstruct the Aristotelian theory of the interdepend ence of form and matter, that form is always form of (or in) matter, and that matter is always for form. The relativity of form and matter, or of form and content, is indeed almost a commonplace of popular discussion on logical subjects. But like other uncritical applications of great truths, this is both carried beyond its proper bounds, and is not carried out with sufficient thoroughness. There cannot — it is said— be a formal logic, because every exercise of thought is internally affected or modified by the material — the subject-matter —with which it deals. It is implied in such an argu ment that the ' subject-matter ' finds no difficulty in existing by itself, but that the ' thought ' is a mere vacuity or un-characterised something which owes its every character to the said matter. But a subject- matter which has content and character has therefore form : it is already known, already thought. And as to this thought, which is said to approach its matter with a self so blank, so impartial, so neutral — what is it? It is a thought or a thinking which has never as yet thought, — which is only named 'thought' by right of expectation, but is itself nothing actual. Of such — fictitious — thought there can hardly be a science. On the other hand, that may be easily called a formal logic, which is much more than formal : and that may be called material, which is only a species of formal. Great indeed is the virtue of names, to suppress and to replace thought. When forms hang on as myste rious names after their day is passed — when they are retained in a certain honour, while the real working methods have assumed other titles ; then these forms become purely formal and antiquated. Thus the Logic of Aristotle seemed in its unfamiliar language to a later xxvi.] FORM AND MATTER. 367 generation to be purely formal and superfluous. It was only another side of the same mistake when the new forms — the forms efficient and active in matter, — were not recognised as formal, but were boldly styled material : and the Logic which discussed such matter-marked forms was called a material Logic. The phrase Matter of Thought, like its many con geners, is a fruitful mother of misconceptions. Caught up by the pictorial imagination, which is always at hand to anticipate thought, it suggests a matter, which is not thought, but is there, all the same, lying in expectation of it. It suggests two things— (for are there not two words, and a preposition or term of relation between them ?). But there are not two things. This matter is just as much a nonentity as the aforesaid thought : a matter of thought is a thought matter, — matter, thought once, and possibly to be thought again. All this talk about the Relativity of form and matter is insincere, and semi-conventional. It is (like the well- known antithesis between Matter and Mind, of which indeed it is only a variation) a halting between two views. That which it chiefly leans to, is that there can be no form without matter, though there may well be matter which is not yet formed. At the best it goes no further than to admit or assert that besides the one there is also the other. It establishes a see-saw, and is proud of it. This is Dualism. Its maxim is, Don't forget that there is an Other. You have explored the One : you have perhaps done well. But there is also and always the Other. The second view is not the mere negation of this dualism. That there is a dualism is a fact which it acknowledges *. All life and reality i manifested in dualism — in antithesis : but the life an the reality is one. Mind— Getst— actualised and intel- 1 Encycl. § 574 (Philosophy of Mind, p. 196). 368 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. ligent experience — is the one ultimate and essential reality \ In the face of its unity, mere matter is only a half-truth, and mere thought is only another. The reality, the unity, and the truth, is matter as formed, nature as reflected in mind. In the reality of experi ence there is always the presence of thought : and thought is only real when it is wedded with nature in the truth of man's mind. So far Bacon and Hegel coincide. Man— in so far as he is Mind — and of course Mind in its fullness is not merely subjective nor merely objective, but absolute — is the measure of all things, the central and comprehensive reality. Such a man— and such a mind— is, we need hardly add, not the man in the street, nor the man in the study : but the infinite, universal, eternal mind in whom these and all others essentially have their being. Such truth of Man — such Mind — is the Absolute : it is sometimes named God : it is the ideal of all aspiration, and the fountain of all truth. 'Logic,' says Hegel2, 'is the science of the Idea in the medium of mere thought.' It exhibits the truth in one partial aspect, or shows one appearance of the total unity of the world, — the aspect it would wear if we could for a moment suppose the reality of Nature to vanish out of sight, and the ideality of Mind reduced to a ghost. It dissects the underlying organisation — the scheme of unification — which the world of mental or spiritual experience presents in all its concreteness. And it does so because it exhibits the last result of the ever clearer and clearer experience which Mind achieves as it comes to see and realise itself. The logical skeleton is the sublimated product of a rich concrete experience. It has been a curious delusion of some who were probably satisfied by a casual glance at Hegel's Logic, especially in its earlier chapters, to suppose that the Logic was 1 Encycl. § 377. 2 Logic, vol. ii. p. 30. XXVI .] LOGIC AND PHILOSOPHY. 369 meant to be the absolute beginning : and that pure or mere thought was the congenital endowment of the heaven-born philosopher1. To Hegel, on the contrary,^ Logic was an abstraction from a fuller, more concrete reality. He did not indeed suppose that the symbolical conception of Movement — in its popular pictorialness — would be an adequate substitute or representative for thought ; but he knew that the energy of mental develop ment was the fact, and the truth, of which 'becoming* is a meagre, abstract phase. Logic, then, is not the Science of mere or pure^K thought, but of the Idea (which is co-terminous with reality) — of the Mind's synthetic unity of experience- looked at, however, abstractly, in the medium of pure thought. Just so, Nature-philosophy is the same Idea, as it turns up bit after bit distracted, fragmentary, and more or less mutilated, in the multiplication, the time and space division, of physical phenomena. But as science requires us to go from the simple to the more complex, as the truth has to prove itself true, by serving in its conclusion as the corroboration of all its premisses or presuppositions ; so the system of philosophy begins with the Logic. Yet it can only begin there, because it has already apprehended itself in its completeness : and it can only move onward because it is the concentrated essence — the implicit being — of all that it actually and explicitly is. It may appear to emerge from a point : but that point has at its back the intellectual unity of a philosophy which embraces the world. It pre supposes the complete philosopher who shall be the complete organ of absolute intelligence, of universal and eternal Spirit. 1 The criticisms of A. Trendelenburg, in his Logische Unter- suchungen, rest on such assumptions. 'Trendelenburg,' says Hart- mann, ' means low-water mark in German philosophy.' Bb 370 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. * A satisfactory Logic then presupposes or implies a complete system of philosophy. No doubt, for a logic which deals with the minor problems of ratiocination or formal induction, all that is needed is a certain general acquaintance with popular conceptions, and with the results or methods of physical science. But if logic takes its business seriously, it must go behind these presuppositions. It must trace back reasoning to its roots, fibres, and first principles. And to do that it is not enough to put at the front a psychological chapter. Far from helping, psychology in these matters is much more in need of being helped itself. Till it has learned a little of the puzzle of the one and the many, the same and the diverse, being, quality, and essence, psychology will be as little use to Logic as blind guides generally are. Nor need this prevent us from saying that when psychology has thoroughly learned these mysteries, it will give fresh life and reality to the logic which it touches upon. The principles of Logic lie in another field1, and are deeper in 'the ground, than obvious psychological gossip. If Logic then deals with form, it deals with a form of forms — the form of the world, of life, and of reality. It is a form, which is a unity in diversity, an organism, — a form which is infinitely manifold, and yet in all its multiplicity one. Logic is the morphology of thought, — of that thought which in Nature is concealed under the variety and divisions of things, and which in the theory of mental and spiritual life is resumed into a complete biology of the world-organism. The problem of Logic then demands an abstraction — an effort of self- concentration — an effort by which the whole machinery of the sensible universe shall be left behind, and the 1 See above all Bradley's Principles of Logic, and Bosanquet's Logic, &c. xxvi.] THE FORM OF THOUGHT. 37 ! accustomed clothing of our thoughts be removed. To move in this ether of pure thought is clearly one of the hardest of problems. Like Plato, we may occasionally feel that we have caught a glimpse of the super-sensible world unveiled ; but it disappears as the senses regain their hold. We can probably fix a firm eye on one term of reason, and criticise its value : but it is less easy to survey the Bacchic dance from term to term1, and allow them to criticise themselves. The distracting influence of our associations, or of outside things, is always leading us astray. Either we incline to treat thoughts as psycho logical products or species, the outcome of a mental process, which are (a) given to us from the beginning, and so a priori or innate, or which (b) spring up in the course of experience by mutual friction between our mind and the outside world, and so are a posteriori or derivative. Or disregarding the subjective side of thoughts, we act as if they were more correctly called things : we speak of relations between phenomena : we suppose things, and causes, and quantities to form part of the so-called external universe, which science ex plores. The one estimate of thought, like the other, keeps in view, though at some distance, and so as not to interfere with their practical discussions, the separate and equal existence of thoughts and things. The psychologists or subjectivists of logic scrutinise the world within us first of all, and purpose to accomplish what can be done for the mind as possessing a faculty of thought, before they turn to the world of things. The realists or objectivists of logic think it better for 'Das Wahre ist der bacchantische Taumel, an dem kein Glied nicht trunken ist ; und weil jedes, indem es sich absondert, ebenso unmittelbar sich auflOst, — ist es ebenso die durchsichtige und ein- fache Ruhe.' Phenom. des Geistes, p. 35. B b 2 372 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. practical work to allow thought only the formal or outside labour of surveying and analysing the laws of phenomena out of the phenomena which contain them. Neither of them examines thought—' the original syn thetic unity' — in its own integrity as a movement in its own self, an inner organisation, of which subject and object, the mind and the things called external, are the vehicles, or, in logical language, the accidents. If it is possible to treat the history of the English Constitution as an object of inquiry in itself and for its own sake, without reference to the individuals who in course of time marred and mended it, or to the setting of events in which its advance is exhibited, why not treat the thought, which is the universal element of all things, of English Constitution, and Italian Art, and Greek Philosophy, in the same way, — absolutely, i. e. in itself and for its own sake? When that is done, distinctions rigidly sustained between a priori and a posteriori become meaningless because now seen to belong to a distinction of earlier and later in the history of the individual consciousness. There is at best only a modified justification for such mottoes and cries, as 'Art for Art's sake,' or 'Science must be left free and unchecked,' or ' The rights of the religious conscience ought always to be respected ' : but there can be no demur or limitation to the cry that Thought must be studied in Thought by Thought and for the sake of Thought. For Art, and Science, and Religion are specialised modes in which the totality or truth of things presents itself to mankind, and none of them can claim an unconditioned sway : their claims clash, and each must be admitted to be after all a partial interpretation, a more or less one-sided interpretation of the true reality of the world. Thought on the other hand is unlimited : for it exists not merely in its own abstract XXVI.] THOUGHT AND REALITY. 373 modes, but interpenetrates and rules all the other concrete forms of experience, manifesting itself in Art and Religion, not less than in Science. And thus when we study Thought, we study that which is in itself anc for itself, — we study Absolute Being. On the other side it must be noted that in Logic it is Absolute Being, only when and as it is thought, which we study. The two sides, Being and Thought, must both come forward : and come in unity, although in some phases of the Idea the thought-element, in others the being-element is more pronounced. Thought, too, is Being. An old distinction of the Stoics, which not inaptly represents popular views on this matter, set on one side 6Va, existences (which were always corporeal, whether they were the things we touch and feel, or the words and breathings by which we utter them), and on the other side the meanings or thoughts proper or o-?7^aii/o>em (which were incorporeal). These Xe/crd, as they were otherwise called, were to the Stoics the proper sphere of Logic. In the sense there fore which the Stoics and popular consciousness give to being, the object of logic does not possess being. It is not corporeal. It cannot however be said to be in the sphere of non-being. It is rather a part of reality — of concrete being — which can be considered apart, as if it stood alone. Alone it does not stand. And yet it holds a position so fundamental, — is the same theme again and again repeated under endless variations, — is so obviously the universal of things— that it may pro perly form the subject of independent study. It is, moreover, a part of Reality, which may well claim to stand for the whole. It is, so to say, the score of the musical composition, rolled up in its bare, silent, unadorned lineaments; the articulated theme, besides, and not the mere germinal concept, of all the variety of 374 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. melody. But it is only laid up there in abstracto, because in the soul of the composer it had already taken concrete form, due to his capacity and training, his mental force, his art and science. It is there that the score has its source. But secondly, the musical work exists in the performance of the orchestra : in the manipulations of the several instruments, in the notes of the singers, in all the diversity of parts which make up the mechanism for unfolding the meaning or theme —that unreality, that mere thought, which to the stricter Stoic might be said to have no vnapfrs, or bodily subsist ence. And there are still people who will be disposed to assert that it is only in the multitude of notes of violin, trombone, flute, &c., that the music is real : — though perhaps these hardy realists do not quite mean what they say. For what they probably mean, and what is the fact, is that the music exists as a complete reality in those who have ears and minds capable of comprehending and enjoying it : in those who can re unite meaning and theme to execution and orchestra tion : and we may even add that it is more and more real, in proportion to the greater power with which they can bring these two into one. We shall rather say then that thought points to reality, and that mere nature seeks for interpretation : that mere thought and mere being both seek for re union. Yet if in the complete reality we thus dis tinguish two elements, we may follow Hegel in setting the pure Idea first. It is no doubt in a way true that, as has been said, Hegel may be often read most easily if we first begin with his concluding paragraphs. In psychology and ethics the fundamental principles have assumed a more imposing, a larger, a more humanly- interesting shape, than they bear in the intangible out lines of Logic. There they are written in blacker ink XXVI.] THOUGHT AND REALITY. 375 and broader lines than in the grey on grey. But after all, it is only for those who have grasped the faint — yet fixed— outlines that the full-contoured figure speaks its amplest truth. The true sculptor must begin with a thorough study of anatomy. For those therefore who do not care merely for results, it is indispensable to begin — or at least to turn back to the beginning — to the Logic. No doubt the full tones of the heard and sounded harmony are the true and adequate presentation of the composer's purpose : but they will be best comprehended and appreciated by those who have thoroughly grasped the score. In Logic, so regarded, thought is no longer merely our thought. It is the constructive, relational, unifying element of reality. Without it reality would not articu lately be anything for us : and such thoughts seem to be its net extract, its quintessence, its concentrated mean ing. But really they are only the potent form of reality. Or, more exactly, in its limits, under its phases, must come all reality if it is to be part and parcel of our intelligent possession, our certified property. Such a thought is the frame-work, the shape-giver of our world, of our communicable experience. It is the formative principle of our intelligent life, as it is the principle through which things have meaning for us, and we have meaning for and fellowship with others. It is not so rich as religion and art, perhaps it does not have the intensity of feeling and faith : but it is at the very basis of all of these, or it is the concentrated essence of what in them is explicated and developed. Humanity in these its highest energies is more than mere thought — more than mere logic : but it is still at the root thought, and it is still governed by the laws and movement of this higher logic. For this is a logic which is no mere instrument of technical reasoning, for 376 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. proof or disproof: no mere code of rules for the evalua tion of testimony. It is a logic which deals with a thought — or an Idea in thought-form — which is the principle of all life and reality: the way of self-criticism which leads to truth : a thought which is at home in all the phases and provinces of experience. Under the same name, Logic, therefore, we find something quite different from what the example of Aristotle and his ancient and modern followers had accustomed us to \ Under the auspices of Kant and his ' Transcendental logic ' there has emerged the need of something more corresponding to the title. For the word itself was not used either by Aristotle or the Stoics. Neither the Analytics and Topics of the one, nor the Dialectic of the other, exhaust the conception of the science, or, to put it more accurately, they are only inceptions of a science, the fulfilment of which was reserved for a later time. Bacon and Locke, Descartes and Spinoza, all the thinkers of modern Europe call for a deeper probing of the logical problem : for a grasp of it which shall be more worthy of its conventional name, Logic, the theory of Reason. And we may even say that what is wanted is a unifica tion of the problem of the Organon with that of the first philosophy, a unification of Logic with Meta physics : a recognition that the problem of reason is not merely the method of reasoning, but the whole theory as to the correlations of perception and concep tion, of thinking and reality. This conception of Logic as the self-developing system of Thought pure and entire, is the distinctive achievement of Hegel. 'I cannot imagine/ he says, ' that the method which I have followed in this system of Logic, or rather the method which this system follows 1 Prantl, Geschichte der Logik, i. 87. XXVI.] THE SCOPE OF LOGIC. 377 in its own self, is otherwise than susceptible of much improvement, and many completions of detail : but I know at the same time that it is the only genuine method. This is evident from the circumstance that it is nothing distinct from its object and subject-matter : for it is the subject-matter within itself, or its inherent dialectic, which moves it along1/ But how is this universe of thought to be discovered, and its law of movement to be described ? From times beyond the reach of history, from nations and tribes of which we know only by tradition and vague con jectures, in all levels of social life and action, the synthetic energy of thought has been productive, and its evolution in the field of time has been going on. For thousands of years the intellectual city has been rearing its walls : and much of the process of its for mation lies beyond the scope of observation. But fortunately there is a help at hand, which will enable us to discover at least the main outlines in the system of thought. The key to the solution was found somewhat in the same way as led to the Darwinian theory concerning the Origin of Species. When the question touching the causes of variation and persistence in the natural kinds of plants and animals seemed so complex as to baffle all attempts at an answer, Darwin found what seemed a clue likely to lead to a theory of descent. The methods adopted in order to keep up, or to vary, a species under domestication were open to anybody's inspection: and those principles, which were consciously pursued in artificial selection by the breeder, suggested a theory of similar selection in free nature. In study ing the phenomena of thought, of which the species or types were no less numerous and interesting than 1 Wissenschaft der Logik, i. p. 39. 378 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. those in organic nature, it was perhaps impossible to survey the whole history of humanity. But it was comparatively easy to observe the process of thought in those cases where its growth had been fostered con sciously and distinctly. The history of philosophy records the steps in the conscious and artificial manipu lation of what for the far greater part is transacted in the silent workshops of nature. Philosophy, in short, is to the general growth of intelligence what artificial breeding is to the variation of species under natural conditions. In the successive systems of phi losophy, the order and concatenation of ideas was, as it were, clarified out of the perturbed medium of real life, and expressed in its bare equivalents in terms of thought, and thus first really acquired. Half of his task was already performed for the logician, and there remained the work, certainly no slight one — of showing the unity and organic development which marked the conscious reasoning, and of connecting it with the general movement of human thought. The logician had to break down the rigid lines which separated one system of philosophy from another, — to see what was really involved in the contradiction of one system by its successor, — and to show that the negation thus given to an antecedent principle was a definite negation, ending not in mere zero or vacuity, but in a distinct result, and making an advance upon the previous height of intelligence. To say this was to give a new value to the history of philosophy. For it followed that each system was no mere opinion or personal view, but was in the main a genuine attempt of the thinker to give expression to the tacit or struggling consciousness of his age. Be hind the individual — who is often unduly regardless of his contemporaries and predecessors, and who writes XXVI.] HISTORY OF PHILOSOPHY. 379 or thinks with little knowledge or sympathy for them, there is the general bearing and interest of the age, its powerful solidarity of purpose and conception. The philosopher is the prophet, because he is in a large part the product of his age. He is an organ of the mind of his age and nation ; and both he and it play a part in the general work of humanity. On the other hand, it is dangerous to insist too forcibly on the rationality of the history of philosophy. For it may be taken to mean — probably only by blinded or wooden commentators — that each step in the evo lution and concatenation of the logical idea is to be identified with some historical system, and that these systems must have appeared in this precise order. And this would be to expect too much from the ' impotence of nature' which plays its part in the historical world also : as that on one side forms part of the Natural. There is Reason in the world— and in the world of history ; but not in the pellueid brightness and distinct outlines proper to the Idea in the abstract element of thought. It may take several philosophers to make one step in thought ; and sometimes one philosopher of genius may take several steps at once. There may even be co-eval philosophies : and there may be philo sophies which appear to run on in independent or parallel lines of development. It may well be that Hegel has underestimated these divergencies, and that he has been too apt to see in all history the co-oper ation to one dominant purpose. But these errors in the execution of a philosophy of history, and especially of the history of philosophy, should not diminish our estimate of its principle \ 1 See Encydop. § 549 (Philosophy of Mind, pp. 148 seqq.). It is, of course, quite another question — to be answered by intelligent research — how far in particular cases Hegel has accurately studied a thinker, 380 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvi. At first this process was seen in the medium of time. But the conditions of time are of practical and particular interest only. The day when the first leaves appear, and the season when the fruit ripens on a tree, are questions of importance to practical arboriculture. But botany deals only with the general theory of the plant's development, in which such considerations have to be generalised. So logic leaves out of account those points of time and chance which the interests of individuals and nations find all-important. And when this element of time has been removed, there is left a system of the types of thought pure and entire, — embalming the life of generations in mere words. The same self- identical thought is set forth from its initial narrowness and poverty on to its final amplitude and wealth of differences. At each stage it is the Absolute : outside of it there is nothing. It is the whole, pure and entire: always the whole. But in its first totality it is all but a void : in its last a fully-formed and articulated world, —because it holds all that it ever threw out of itself resumed into its grasp. In these circumstances nothing can sound higher and nobler than the Theory of Logic. It presents the Truth unveiled in its proper form and absolute nature. If the philosopher may call this absolute totality of thought ever staying the same in its eternal development,— this adequacy of thought to its own requirements — by the name of God, then we may say with Hegel that Logic exhibits God as He is in His eternal Being before the creation of Nature and a finite Mind l. But the logical Idea is only a phantom Deity and faithfully interpreted him. Some of his critics in this line appear to mistake philology — which is a highly important authority in its own field — for philosophy : and will no doubt go on doing so. 1 Hegel's Werke, iii. 33. XXVI.] THE SCOPE OF LOGIC. 381 — the bare possibility of a God or of absolute reality in all the development of its details. The first acquaintance with the abstract theory is likely to dash cold water on the enthusiasm thus awakened, and may sober our views of the magic efficacy of Logic. ' The student on his first approach to the Science/ says Hegel, 'sees in Logic at first only one system of abstractions apart and limited to itself, not extending so as to include other facts and sciences. On the contrary, when it is contrasted with the variety abounding in our generalised picture of the world, and with the tangible realities embraced in the other sciences, — when it is compared with the promise of the Absolute Science to lay bare the essence of that variety, the inner nature of the mind and the world, or, in one word, the Truth, — this science of Logic in its abstract outline, in the colourless cold simplicity of its mere terms of thought, seems as if it would perform anything sooner than this promise, and in the face of that variety seems very empty indeed. A first intro duction to the study of Logic leads us to suppose that its significance is restricted to itself. Its doctrines are not believed to be more than one separate branch of study engaged with the terms or dimensions of thought, besides which the other scientific occupations have a proper material and body of their own. Upon these occupations, it is assumed, Logic may exert a formal influence, but it is the influence of a natural and spon taneous logic for which the scientific form and its study may be in case of need dispensed with. The other sciences have upon the whole rejected the regulation- method, which made them a series of definitions, axioms, and theorems, with the demonstration of these theorems. What is called Natural Logic rules in the sciences with full sway, and gets along without any special investi- 382 PROLEGOMENA. gation in the direction of thought itself. The entire materials and facts of these sciences have detached themselves completely from Logic. Besides they are more attractive for sense, feeling, or imagination, and for practical interests of every description. ' And so it comes about that Logic has to be learned at first, as something which is perhaps understood and seen into, but of which the compass, the depth, and further import are in the earliest stages unperceived. It is only after a deeper study of the other sciences that logical theory rises before the mind of the student into a universal, which is not merely abstract, but embraces within it the variety of particulars. — The same moral truth on the lips of a youth, who under stands it quite correctly, does not possess the significance or the burden of meaning which it has in the mind of the veteran, in whom the experience of a lifetime has made it express the whole force of its import. In the same way, Logic is not appreciated at its right value until it has grown to be the result of scientific experience. It is then seen to be the universal truth, — not a special study beside other matters and other realities, but the essence of all these other facts to gether1/ 1 Wissenschaft der Logik, i. p. 43. CHAPTER XXVII. ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE I OR THE CATEGORIES. ACCORDING to the strict reasonings of Kant in his Criticism of Pure Reason, and the somewhat looser discussions of Mr. Spencer in his First Principles a science of Metaphysics or theory of the Infinite, Absolute, or Unconditioned is impossible. As a result of the criticism by Kant, Jacobi claimed the Absolute for Faith : and Spencer banishes the Absolute or Un knowable to the sphere of Religion to be worshipped or ignored, but in either case blindly. As we have already seen, Hegel does not accept this distribution of provinces between religion and philosophy. There is only one world, one reality : but it is known more or less fully, more or less truly and adequately. It is presented in one way to the sensuous imagination : in another to the scientific analyst: in a third to the philosopher. To the first it is a mere succession or expanse of pictures, facts, appearances: and outside it— somewhere, but not here,— there is a land, a being of perfect wholeness and harmony. To the second it is an unending chain of causes^and effects, of one thing simplified by being referred to another till at last a mighty all-explaining nullity, called an ' Ultimate Cause/ is presumed to linger, eternally unperceived at the infinitely-distant end of the scries. To the third 384 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvil. everything is seen in connexion, but not a mere unilinear connexion : each, when studied, more and more com pletes itself by including those relations which seemed to stand outside : each fully realised, or completely invested with its ideal implications, is seen no longer to be an incident or isolated fact, but an implicit infinite, and a vice-gerent of the eternal. Philosophy thus releases both ordinary and scientific knowledge from their limitations; it shows the finite passing into the infinite. And Hegel, accordingly, purposes to show that this unfathomable Absolute is very near us, and at our very door : in our hands, as it were, and especially present in our every-day language. If we are ever to gain the Absolute, we must be careful not to lose one jot or tittle of the Relative \ The Absolute —this term, which is to some so offensive and to others so precious — always presents itself to us in Relatives : and when we have persistently traced the Proteus through all its manifestations, — when we have, so to speak, seen the Absolute Relativity of Relation, there is very little more needed in order to apprehend the Absolute pure and entire. One may say of the Absolute what Goethe2 says of Nature: 'She lives entirely in her children : and the mother, where is she?' It is a great step, when we have detected the Rela tivity of what had hitherto seemed Absolute, — when a new aspect of the infinite fullness of the world, the truth of things, dawns upon us. But it is even a greater step when we see that the Relativity which we have 1 Cf. Herbart's maxim, ' Wie viel Schein, so viel Hindeutung auf Sein.' (Hauptpunkte der Metophysik.} 2 Die Natur (1780) : ' Sie lebt in lauter Kindern : und die Mutter, wo ist sie? . . . . Sie ist ganz und doch immer unvollendet. . . . Sie verbirgt sich in tausend Namen und Termen, und ist immer dieselbe.' xxvii.] ABSOLUTE AND RELATIVE. 385 thus discovered is itself Relative. And this is one advantage of first studying the value of the categories of ethics and physics on Logical ground. On the concreter region of Nature and Mind; the several grades and species into which reality is divided have a portentous firmness and grandeur about them, and the intrinsic dialectic seems scarcely adequate to shaking the foundations of their stability. They severally stand as independent self-sustaining entities, separate from each other, and stereotyped in their several formations. But in the ether of abstract Idea, in the fluid and transparent form of mere thoughts, the several stages in the development of the Absolute, the various grades of category, clearly betray their Rela tivity, and by the negation of this Relativity lead on to a higher Absolute. To the practical man, — so long as his reflection does not go deep,— the concepts on which his knowledge and faith are built seem eternal, unshifting rock, parts of the inmost fabric of things. He accepts them as ultimate validities. To him matter and force, cause and effect, distinctions between form and content, whole and part, quantity and quality, belong to the final con stitution of the world. (And so, in a sense, they do.) If he ever overcome the absoluteness which popular thought attributes to the individual things of sense and imagination, and show their relativity, he does so only to fall under the glamour of a new deception. Causes and matters, forces and atoms, become new ultimates, new absolutes, of another order. Fictions or postulates of the understanding take the place of the figments of imagination. The ordinary scientific man labours especially under the 'metaphysical' fallacy: he realises abstractions in their abstractness. As against this it is the business of the logician to show how such c c 386 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvii. terms are to be interpreted as steps in a process of interpretation — containing so much that others of simpler structure have handed on, and themselves presupposing by implication a great deal they fail properly to explicate. Thus, the logician evinces at one blow the relativity of each term in its mereness, abstractness, or false absoluteness, and the ideal abso luteness which always carries it beyond itself, and makes it mean more than it says. The natural mind always hastens to substantiate the terms it employs. It makes them a fixed, solid found ation, an hypostasis, on which further building may be raised. If such pseudo-absolutising of concepts is to be called metaphysics, then logic has to free us from the illusions of metaphysics, to de-absolutise them, to disabuse us of a false Absolute. The false Absolute is what Hegel calls the Abstract : it is the part which, because it succeeded in losing sight of its dependence, had believed itself to be a whole. Logic shows — in the phrase of Hegel — that each such term or concept is only an attempt to express, explicate, or define the Absolute J : a predicate of the Absolute, but falling short of its subject, or only uttering part of the whole truth of reality. But while Logic shows it only to be an attempt, and therefore in an aspect relative, it equally shows its ingrained tendency to complete itself, to carry out to realisation its ideal implication,— shows, in short, that e. g. force is more than mere force, that thing-in-itself is not properly even a thing ; that a veritable notion (Begriff) or grasp of a thing is more than a mere (subjective) notion, &c. Thus the true Absolute is not the emptiest and most meagre of abstractions, — what is left as a residual after the relative in all its breadth and length has been cut out of it ; 1 Logic (Encyclop.} §§ 85, 87, 112, 194, &c. XXVII.] LOGIC AND METAPHYSICS. 387 it is the concretest of all being, the whole which includes without destroying all partial aspects. Yet as it includes them, it shows itself their master and more than master: making each lose and win in the other, till all are satisfied in unity, and no shade of individuality is utterly lost in the totality of the Universal. Accordingly, Metaphysics and Logic tend to form one body. For the distant and transcendent Absolute, which was the object of older Metaphysics, was sub stituted an Absolute, self-revealing in the terms of thought. Being is deposed from its absoluteness, and made the first postulate of thought. Former Meta physics had dashed itself in vain against the reefs that girdle the island of the supersensible and noumenal, the supposed world of true Being: and the struggle at last grew so disastrous that Kant gave the signal to retreat, and to leave the world of true Being, the impregnable Thing-in-itself, to its repose. His ad vice to metaphysicians1 was that, while scientific re search continued to concentrate the attack of analysis upon single experiences conforming to certain con ditions, they should investigate these conditions of possible experience or foundations of objectivity. In other words, he turned observation to what he called Transcendental Logic. It was by means of this sug gestion, understood in the widest sense, that Hegel was led to treat Logic as the science of ultimate reality. He had to show how these conditions when carried out in full gave the Unconditioned. He attacked the Absolute, if we may say so, in detail. The Ab- solute, as the totality, universe or system of Relativity, 1 Metaphysic is, in Kant's usage, ambiguous. It means («) a sup posed science of the supersensible or unconditioned reality; (6) a study of the conditions or presuppositions— the Kantian a priori— of some aspect of Experience, e. g. a Metaphysic of Moral rules. C C 2 388 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvn. lays itself open to observation by deposing itself to a Relative. It possesses the differentiating power of separating itself as an object in passivity, from itself as a subject in action,— of deposing itself to appearance, of being for itself, and also in and for itself. And thus Thought is the active universal,— which actualises itself more and more out of abstraction into concreteness. Hegel, then, solved the problem of Metaphysics by turning it into Logic. The same principle, Thought, appeared in both : in the former as a fixed and passive result, showing no traces of spontaneity, — in the latter as an activity, with a mere power of passing from object to object, discovering and establishing connexions and relations. The two sciences were fragments, unintelli gible and untenable, when taken in abstract isolation. This is the justification, if justification be required, for Hegel's unification of Logic and Metaphysics. The Hegelian Logic falls into three parts: the theory of Transitory Being : the theory of Relative Being : and the theory of the Notion. The first and second of these in his Science of Logic are called Objective Logic ; they also might be described as- Metaphysics. The third part is more strictly on Logical ground. Or perhaps it is best to describe the whole as the Meta physics of Logic. The Logic of Hegel is the Science of Thought as an organic system of its characteristic forms, which in their entirety constitute the Idea. These forms or types of thought, the moulds in which the Idea confines itself in its evolution, are not unlike what have been otherwise called the Categories. (Of course the foreign word ' Categories' does not commend itself to Hegel) \ They 1 His usual term is Denk-bestimmungen, the several expressions or specific forms of the unification which thought is. The term Categories has been identified by Kant with his list of Stammbegriffe, XXVII-J THE CATEGORIES. 3_89 are the modifications or definite forms, the articulated and distinct shapes, in which the process of Thought ever and anon culminates in the course of its movement. The Infinite and Absolute at these points conditions itself, and as so conditioned or differentiated is appre hended and stamped with a name. They specify the unspecified, and give utterance to the ineffable. They are the names by which reason grasps the totality of things,— the names by which the truth (or God) reveals itself, however inadequately. From one point of view they constitute a series, each evolved from the other, a more completely detailed term or utterance of thought resulting by innate contradiction from a less detailed. From another point of view the total remains per petually the same ; and the change seems only on the surface. The one aspect of the movement conceals the Absolute : the other puts the Relative into the back ground. What then are the Categories? We may answer: They are the ways in which expression is given to the unifying influence of thought : and we have to consider them as points or stations in the progress of this unifica tion, and in the light of this influence. These Categories are the typical structures marking the definite grades in the growth of thought,— the moulds or forms which thought assumes and places itself in,— those instants when the process of thought takes a determinate form, and admits of being grasped. The growth of thought, like other growths, is often imperceptible and impal- and by Mill with his classes of nameable things,— with some critical remarks on Aristotle's use of the word. That use-to denote the elements of predicable reality, what Grote called ens— is probably not so « rhapsodical ' as Kant, with his new-born zeal for the contrast of sensibility and intellect, was inclined to suppose. A real history of the Category-theory would be almost a history of philosophy. Perhaps the name might be more sparingly used. 390 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvil. pable. And then, unexpectedly, a condensation takes place, a form is precipitated out of the transparent medium. A new concept, a new grasp of reality, emerges from the solution of elements : and a name is created to realise the new shade of the Idea. These thought-terms are the world of Platonic forms, if we consider his ' form of Good ' as corresponding to the ' Idea ' of Hegel. For if we look carefully into this mystic word ' Good ' which plays so brilliant a part in ancient philosophy, we shall see that it only expresses in a more concrete and less analytic form, as ancient thought often does, the same thing as so many moderns love to speak of as Relativity, and which is also implied in Aristotle's conception of an End. To see things sub specie boni— which Plato describes as the supreme quality of the truth-seeker who is to guide men into uprightness, or into conformity with the true nature of things,— is to see them elevated above their partial self-subsistence into the harmony and totality of that which is always and unvaryingly its real self. The Good is the sun-light in which things lose their earlier character (which they had in the days of our bondage and ignorance) of mysterious and perplexing spectres of the night. In the light of the Good, things are shorn of their false pretence of self-subsistence and substantiality, deposed by comparison with the perfect and unspotted, and as it were stung into seeking a higher form of being by struggle. And this is the abstract moral way of looking. But to see them in the form of Good means also that they are seen to be more and better than we thought, that they are not con demned to inadequacy, but bear in them the witness and revelation of infinity and absoluteness. And this is rather the faith of religion and the vision of art. And the ' form of Good ' is only a brief and undeveloped XXVIL] THE CATEGORIES. 3pl vision of an Absolute, which is the 'form of Relativity/ —Relativity elevated into an Absolute. A Category is often spoken of as if it were the highest extreme of generalisation, the most abstract and most widely applicable term possible. If we climb sufficiently far and high up the Porphyry's tree of thought, we may expect,^ thought the old logicians, to reach the ' summa genera' or highest species of human thought. Nor have modern logicians always refrained from this byway. But these quantitative distinctions of greater and less, in which the Formal Logic revels, are not very suitable to any of the terms or processes of thought, and they certainly give an imperfect descrip tion of the Categories. The essential function which the Categories perform in the fabric of thought and language is, in the first place, to combine, affirm, demon strate, relate, and unify, — and not to generalise \ Their action may be better compared to that fulfilled by those symbols in an algebraical expression, which like plus and minus denote an operation to be performed in the way of combining or relating, than to the office of the symbols which in these expressions denote the magni tudes themselves. To the student of language the Categories sometimes present themselves as pronominal, or formal roots,— those roots which, as it is said, do not denote things, but relations between things. He meets them in the in flections of nouns and verbs ; in the signs of number, gender, case, and person : but, as thus presented, their influence is subordinate to the things of which they are, as it were, the accidents. He meets them in a more 1 Generalisation is only one small aspect of thought, with speciali sation as its, at least as important, pendant. To read certain logics, one might think the all-comprehensive virtue of truths were to be general, — not to be true. 392 PROLEGOMENA. [xxvii. independent and tangible shape in the articles, pro nouns, prepositions, conjunctions, and numerals, and in what are called the auxiliary verbs. In these apparently trifling, and in some languages almost non-existent words or parts of words, we have the symbols of rela tions, — the means of connexion between single words, —the cement which binds significant speech together. There are languages, such as the older and classical forms of Chinese, where these categorising terms are, as it were, in the air : where they are only felt in accent and position, and have no separate existence of their own. But in the languages of the Indo-European family they gradually appear, at first in combination, perhaps, with the more material roots, and only in the course of time asserting an independent form. Origin ally they appear to denote the relations of space and time, — the generalised or typical links between the parts of our sense-perceptions : but from there they are after wards, and in a little while, transferred into the service of intellect. These little words are the very life-blood of a language, — its spirit and force. It is in these cate gories, as they show themselves in the different linguistic families, that a nation betrays its mode and tone of thought. The language of the Altaic races, e.g., ex presses activity only as a piece of property, an appro priation of a substance, and knows no true distinction of noun and verb : the Semitic Tongues in their tense- system perhaps betray the intense inwardness of the race : whereas the immense inflectionalism of the Indo- European seems not unconnected with his greater versatility and energy. Complete mastery in the mani pulation of these particles and forms is what makes an idiomatic knowledge of a language, as distinct from a mere remembrance of the vocabulary. And philo sophy is the recognition of their import and signifi- xxvii.] CATEGORIES IN LANGUAGE. 393 cance. Thus in Greek philosophy the central questions turn upon such words as Being and not-Being : Becom ing : that out of which : that for the sake of which : the what-was-being : the what is : the other : the one : the great and small : that which is upon the whole : what is according to each : this somewhat : &C.1 And again in Modern Philosophy, how often has the battle raged about the meaning of such words as I : will : can : must : be cause : same and different: self: &c. ! 1 ov and ju/) ov ; TO yiyvu^fvov : TO l£ ov : TO ov evf/ta : TO ri ?/v elvat : TO TI iaTi : 9a.T(pov : age i ,,2 ,,4 ,,6 ,,7 . j j Edited by Dr. Murray Vol. II. C Edited by Dr. Murray £ , 212 1. DICTIONARIES. A New English Dictionary on Historical Prin ciples, founded mainly on the materials collected by the Philo logical Society. Imperial 4to. PRESENT STATE OF THE WORK. Vol. I. -j "j Edited by Dr. Murray .... Half-morocco . . . . Half-morocco 2 D-Deceit o Deceit-Deject o D Edited by Dr. Murray -( Deject-Depravation . . o Depravative-Development o \ Development -Diffluency . o (The remainder of the Idler D is far advanced.} E-Every o 12 Everybody-Ezod F-Fang I F Edited by Mr. Henry Bradley J Fanged-Fee E Edited by Mr. Henry Bradley Vol. IV. Fee-Field .... Field-Fish .... {sfar advanced.} p ^ ^The remain(}er Of the ietter G To be edited by Mr. Henry Bradley. H To be edited by Dr. Murray. j*^ The Dictionary is also, as heretofore, issued in the original Parts, of which the foUoiving are already published : — Series I. Parts I-VII. A-Crouching ..... . . each o 12 „ Part VIII. Crouchmas-Depravation .... o 12 Or in two Fasciculi, Cr-Cz, 45.; D-Depravation, 8s. 6d. Series II. Parti. E-Every ........ o 12 ,, Part II. Everybody-Field ... o 12 Or in two Fasciculi, Everybody-Ezod, 55. ; "F-Field, 75. 6d. Oxford : Clarendon Press. London : HENRY FROWDE, Amen Corner, E.G. ENGLISH AND ROMAN LAW. An Etymological Dictionary of the English Language, arranged on an Historical Basis. By W. W. Skeat, Litt.D, Second Edition. 4to. 27. 4.9. A Middle-English Dictionary. By F. H. Stratmann, A new edition, by H. Bradley, M.A. 4to, half-bound, iZ. us. 6d. An Anglo-Saxon Dictionary, based on the MS. col lections of the late Joseph Bosworth, D.D. Edited and enlarged b) Prof. T. N. Toller, M.A. Parts I-III. A-SiR. 4to, stiff covers, 155 each. Part IV, § i, SAR-SWf DRIAN. Stiff covers, 8s. 6d. An Icelandic-English Dictionary, based on the MS collections of the late Richard Cleasby. Enlarged and completed bj G. Vigfusson, M.A. 4to. $1. ;s. A Sanskrit-English Dictionary. Etymologically anc Philologically arranged. By Sir M. Monier- Williams, D.C.L. 4to 4^. 14.5. 6d. A Hebrew and English Lexicon of the Old Testament, with an Appendix containing the Biblical Aramaic, base( on the Thesaurus and Lexicon of Gesenius, by Francis Brown, D.D. S. R Driver, D.D., and C. A. Briggs, D.D. Parts I-V. Small 4to 2s. 6d. each. Thesaurus Syriacus : collegerunt Quatremere, Bernstein Lorsbach, Arnoldi, Agrell, Field, Roediger : edidit R. Payne Smith S.T.P. Vol. I, containing Fasc. I-V, sm. fol. 5*. 55. Fasc. VI. il. is. ; VII. iZ. us. 6d. ; VIII. il. if>s. ; IX. i7. 55. 2. LAW. Anson. Principles of the English Law of Contract, and of Agency in its Relation to Contract. By Sir W. R. Anson, D.C.L. Eighth Edition. 8vo. I os. 6d. Law and Custom of the Constitution. 2 vols. 8vo. Second Edition. Part I. Parliament. i2s. 6d. Part II. The Crown. 145. Baden-Powell. Land-Systems of British India ; being a Manual of the Land-Tenures, and of the Sys tems of Land-Revenue Adminis tration prevalent in the severa Provinces. By B. H. Baden-Powell C.I.E. 3 vols. 8vo. 32. 35. Baden-Powell. Land-Revenu* and Tenure in British India. By th< same Author. With Map. Crowi 8vo. 55. Digby. An Introduction t( the History of the Law of Real Property By Kenelm E. Digby, M.A. Fourt Edition. 8vo. las. 6d. Greenidge. Infamia;it8plac\ in Roman Public and Private Law. B; A. H. J. Greenidge, M.A. 8 vo. i os. 60 Oxford : Clarendon Press. LA W. 3 Grueber. Lex Aquilla. The Roman Law of Damage to Pro perty : being a Commentary on the Title of the Digest 'Ad Legem Aquiliam ' (ix. 2). By Erwin Grue ber, Dr. Jur., M.A. 8vo. los. 6d. Hall. International Law. i ByW. E. Hall, M.A. Fourth Edition. 8vo. 22s. 6d. — A Treatise on the Foreign j Powers and Jurisdiction of the British >, Crown. By W. E. Hall, M.A. 8vo. j los. 6d. Holland. Elements of Juris- • prudence. By T. E. Holland, D.C.L. j Seventh Edition. 8vo. los. 6d. The European Concert in the Eastern Question; a Collection of Treaties and other Public Acts. Edited, with Introductions and Notes, by T. E. Holland, D.C.L. 8vo. i2s. 6rf. Gentilis, Alberici, De lure Belli Libri Tres. Edidit T. E. Holland, I.C.D. Small 4to, half- morocco, 2 IS. The Institutes of Jus tinian, edited as a recension of the Institutes of Gaius, by T.1 E. Holland, D.C.L. Second Edition. Extra fcap. 8vo. 55. Holland and Shadwell. Select Titles from the Digest of Justinian. By T. E. Holland, D.C.L., and C. L. Shadwell, B.C.L. 8vo. 145. Also sold in Parts, in paper covers :— Part I. Introductory Titles, as. 6d. Part II. Family Law. is. Part III. Property Law. as. 6rf. Part IV. Law of Obligations (No. i ), 3«. 6d. (No. 2), 45. 6d. Markby. Elements of considered with reference to Principles of GeneralJurisprudence. By SirWilliam Markby, D.C.L. Fourth Edition. 8vo. I2s. 6d. Moyle. Imperatoris lus- tiniani Imtitutionum Libri Quattuor ; with Introductions, Commentary, Excursus and Translation. By J. B. Moyle, D.C.L. Second Edition. 2 vols. Svo. Vol. I. i6s. Vol. II. 6.s. Contract of Sale in the Civil Law. By J. B. Moyle, D.C.L. Svo. los. 6d. Pollock and Wright. An Essay on Possession in the Common Law. By Sir F. Pollock, Bart., M.A., and SirR. S.Wright, B.C.L. Svo. 8s. 6d. Poste. Gaii Institutionum Juris Civilis Commentarii Quattuor ; or, Elements of Roman Law by Gaius. With a Translation and Commen tary by Edward Poste, M.A. Third Edition. Svo. iSs. Raleigh. An Outline of the Law of Properly. By Thos. Raleigh, M.A. Svo. 7s. 6d. Sohm. Institutes of Roman Law. By Rudolph Sohm, Professor in the University of Leipzig. Trans lated by J. C. Ledlie, B.C.L. With an Introductory Essay by Erwin Grueber, Dr. Jur., M.A. Svo. i8s. Stokes. The Anglo-Indian Codes. By Whitley Stokes, LL.D. Vol. I. Substantive Law. Svo. 303. Vol. II. Adjective Law. Svo. 355. First and Second Supplements tc the above, 1887-1891. Svo. 6s. 6d ; Separately, No. i, ss.6